10 Edition Biology Mader Pdf

 admin  
  1. Available in: Paperback. The laboratory exercises in this manual are coordinated with HUMAN BIOLOGY,a text that has two primary functions: 1) to.
  2. The College Board is a mission-driven not-for-profit organization that connects students to college success and opportunity. Founded in 1900, the College Board was created to expand access to higher education. Today, the membership association is made up of more than 5,900 of the world's leading educational.
Part of a series on
Evolutionary biology
  • History of paleontology (timeline)
  • Category

Evolution is change in the heritablecharacteristics of biological populations over successive generations.[1][2] These characteristics are the expressions of genes that are passed on from parent to offspring during reproduction. Different characteristics tend to exist within any given population as a result of mutation, genetic recombination and other sources of genetic variation.[3] Evolution occurs when evolutionary processes such as natural selection (including sexual selection) and genetic drift act on this variation, resulting in certain characteristics becoming more common or rare within a population.[4] It is this process of evolution that has given rise to biodiversity at every level of biological organisation, including the levels of species, individual organisms and molecules.[5][6]

1.2 Evolution, the Unifying Concept of. 1.A.1: Natural selection is a major mechanism of evolution. 1.3 How the Biosphere Is Organized. 1.4 The Process of Science. Basic Chemistry. 2.1 Chemical Elements. 2.2 Molecules and Compounds. 4.A.1: The subcomponents of biological.

The scientific theory of evolution by natural selection was proposed by Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace in the mid-19th century and was set out in detail in Darwin's book On the Origin of Species (1859).[7] Evolution by natural selection was first demonstrated by the observation that more offspring are often produced than can possibly survive. This is followed by three observable facts about living organisms: 1) traits vary among individuals with respect to their morphology, physiology and behaviour (phenotypic variation), 2) different traits confer different rates of survival and reproduction (differential fitness) and 3) traits can be passed from generation to generation (heritability of fitness).[8] Thus, in successive generations members of a population are more likely to be replaced by the progenies of parents with favourable characteristics that have enabled them to survive and reproduce in their respective environments. In the early 20th century, other competing ideas of evolution such as mutationism and orthogenesis were refuted as the modern synthesis reconciled Darwinian evolution with classical genetics, which established adaptive evolution as being caused by natural selection acting on Mendelian genetic variation.[9]

All life on Earth shares a last universal common ancestor (LUCA)[10][11][12] that lived approximately 3.5–3.8 billion years ago.[13] The fossil record includes a progression from early biogenicgraphite,[14] to microbial mat fossils,[15][16][17] to fossilised multicellular organisms. Existing patterns of biodiversity have been shaped by repeated formations of new species (speciation), changes within species (anagenesis) and loss of species (extinction) throughout the evolutionary history of life on Earth.[18]Morphological and biochemical traits are more similar among species that share a more recent common ancestor, and can be used to reconstruct phylogenetic trees.[19][20]

Evolutionary biologists have continued to study various aspects of evolution by forming and testing hypotheses as well as constructing theories based on evidence from the field or laboratory and on data generated by the methods of mathematical and theoretical biology. Their discoveries have influenced not just the development of biology but numerous other scientific and industrial fields, including agriculture, medicine and computer science.[21]

  • 1History of evolutionary thought
  • 3Variation
  • 4Mechanisms
  • 5Outcomes
  • 6Evolutionary history of life

History of evolutionary thought

In 1842, Charles Darwin penned his first sketch of On the Origin of Species.[22]

Classical times

The proposal that one type of organism could descend from another type goes back to some of the first pre-Socratic Greek philosophers, such as Anaximander and Empedocles.[23] Such proposals survived into Roman times. The poet and philosopher Lucretius followed Empedocles in his masterwork De rerum natura (On the Nature of Things).[24][25]

Medieval

In contrast to these materialistic views, Aristotelianism considered all natural things as actualisations of fixed natural possibilities, known as forms.[26][27] This was part of a medieval teleological understanding of nature in which all things have an intended role to play in a divinecosmic order. Variations of this idea became the standard understanding of the Middle Ages and were integrated into Christian learning, but Aristotle did not demand that real types of organisms always correspond one-for-one with exact metaphysical forms and specifically gave examples of how new types of living things could come to be.[28]

Pre-Darwinian

In the 17th century, the new method of modern science rejected the Aristotelian approach. It sought explanations of natural phenomena in terms of physical laws that were the same for all visible things and that did not require the existence of any fixed natural categories or divine cosmic order. However, this new approach was slow to take root in the biological sciences, the last bastion of the concept of fixed natural types. John Ray applied one of the previously more general terms for fixed natural types, 'species,' to plant and animal types, but he strictly identified each type of living thing as a species and proposed that each species could be defined by the features that perpetuated themselves generation after generation.[29] The biological classification introduced by Carl Linnaeus in 1735 explicitly recognised the hierarchical nature of species relationships, but still viewed species as fixed according to a divine plan.[30]

Other naturalists of this time speculated on the evolutionary change of species over time according to natural laws. In 1751, Pierre Louis Maupertuis wrote of natural modifications occurring during reproduction and accumulating over many generations to produce new species.[31]Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon suggested that species could degenerate into different organisms, and Erasmus Darwin proposed that all warm-blooded animals could have descended from a single microorganism (or 'filament').[32] The first full-fledged evolutionary scheme was Jean-Baptiste Lamarck's 'transmutation' theory of 1809,[33] which envisaged spontaneous generation continually producing simple forms of life that developed greater complexity in parallel lineages with an inherent progressive tendency, and postulated that on a local level, these lineages adapted to the environment by inheriting changes caused by their use or disuse in parents.[34][35] (The latter process was later called Lamarckism.)[34][36][37][38] These ideas were condemned by established naturalists as speculation lacking empirical support. In particular, Georges Cuvier insisted that species were unrelated and fixed, their similarities reflecting divine design for functional needs. In the meantime, Ray's ideas of benevolent design had been developed by William Paley into the Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity (1802), which proposed complex adaptations as evidence of divine design and which was admired by Charles Darwin.[39][40][41]

Darwinian revolution

The crucial break from the concept of constant typological classes or types in biology came with the theory of evolution through natural selection, which was formulated by Charles Darwin in terms of variable populations. Darwin used the expression 'descent with modification' rather than 'evolution'.[42] Partly influenced by An Essay on the Principle of Population (1798) by Thomas Robert Malthus, Darwin noted that population growth would lead to a 'struggle for existence' in which favourable variations prevailed as others perished. In each generation, many offspring fail to survive to an age of reproduction because of limited resources. This could explain the diversity of plants and animals from a common ancestry through the working of natural laws in the same way for all types of organism.[43][44][45][46] Darwin developed his theory of 'natural selection' from 1838 onwards and was writing up his 'big book' on the subject when Alfred Russel Wallace sent him a version of virtually the same theory in 1858. Their separate papers were presented together at an 1858 meeting of the Linnean Society of London.[47] At the end of 1859, Darwin's publication of his 'abstract' as On the Origin of Species explained natural selection in detail and in a way that led to an increasingly wide acceptance of Darwin's concepts of evolution at the expense of alternative theories. Thomas Henry Huxley applied Darwin's ideas to humans, using paleontology and comparative anatomy to provide strong evidence that humans and apes shared a common ancestry. Some were disturbed by this since it implied that humans did not have a special place in the universe.[48]

Pangenesis and heredity

The mechanisms of reproductive heritability and the origin of new traits remained a mystery. Towards this end, Darwin developed his provisional theory of pangenesis.[49] In 1865, Gregor Mendel reported that traits were inherited in a predictable manner through the independent assortment and segregation of elements (later known as genes). Mendel's laws of inheritance eventually supplanted most of Darwin's pangenesis theory.[50]August Weismann made the important distinction between germ cells that give rise to gametes (such as sperm and egg cells) and the somatic cells of the body, demonstrating that heredity passes through the germ line only. Hugo de Vries connected Darwin's pangenesis theory to Weismann's germ/soma cell distinction and proposed that Darwin's pangenes were concentrated in the cell nucleus and when expressed they could move into the cytoplasm to change the cell's structure. De Vries was also one of the researchers who made Mendel's work well known, believing that Mendelian traits corresponded to the transfer of heritable variations along the germline.[51] To explain how new variants originate, de Vries developed a mutation theory that led to a temporary rift between those who accepted Darwinian evolution and biometricians who allied with de Vries.[35][52][53] In the 1930s, pioneers in the field of population genetics, such as Ronald Fisher, Sewall Wright and J. B. S. Haldane set the foundations of evolution onto a robust statistical philosophy. The false contradiction between Darwin's theory, genetic mutations, and Mendelian inheritance was thus reconciled.[54]

The 'modern synthesis'

Pdf

In the 1920s and 1930s the so-called modern synthesis connected natural selection and population genetics, based on Mendelian inheritance, into a unified theory that applied generally to any branch of biology. The modern synthesis explained patterns observed across species in populations, through fossil transitions in palaeontology, and complex cellular mechanisms in developmental biology.[35][55] The publication of the structure of DNA by James Watson and Francis Crick with contribution of Rosalind Franklin in 1953 demonstrated a physical mechanism for inheritance.[56]Molecular biology improved understanding of the relationship between genotype and phenotype. Advancements were also made in phylogenetic systematics, mapping the transition of traits into a comparative and testable framework through the publication and use of evolutionary trees.[57][58] In 1973, evolutionary biologist Theodosius Dobzhansky penned that 'nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution,' because it has brought to light the relations of what first seemed disjointed facts in natural history into a coherent explanatory body of knowledge that describes and predicts many observable facts about life on this planet.[59]

Further syntheses

Since then, the modern synthesis has been further extended to explain biological phenomena across the full and integrative scale of the biological hierarchy, from genes to species. One extension, known as evolutionary developmental biology and informally called 'evo-devo,' emphasises how changes between generations (evolution) acts on patterns of change within individual organisms (development).[60][61][62] Since the beginning of the 21st century and in light of discoveries made in recent decades, some biologists have argued for an extended evolutionary synthesis, which would account for the effects of non-genetic inheritance modes, such as epigenetics, parental effects, ecological inheritance and cultural inheritance, and evolvability.[63][64]

Heredity

DNA structure. Bases are in the centre, surrounded by phosphate–sugar chains in a double helix.

Evolution in organisms occurs through changes in heritable traits—the inherited characteristics of an organism. In humans, for example, eye colour is an inherited characteristic and an individual might inherit the 'brown-eye trait' from one of their parents.[65] Inherited traits are controlled by genes and the complete set of genes within an organism's genome (genetic material) is called its genotype.[66]

The complete set of observable traits that make up the structure and behaviour of an organism is called its phenotype. These traits come from the interaction of its genotype with the environment.[67] As a result, many aspects of an organism's phenotype are not inherited. For example, suntanned skin comes from the interaction between a person's genotype and sunlight; thus, suntans are not passed on to people's children. However, some people tan more easily than others, due to differences in genotypic variation; a striking example are people with the inherited trait of albinism, who do not tan at all and are very sensitive to sunburn.[68]

Heritable traits are passed from one generation to the next via DNA, a molecule that encodes genetic information.[66] DNA is a long biopolymer composed of four types of bases. The sequence of bases along a particular DNA molecule specify the genetic information, in a manner similar to a sequence of letters spelling out a sentence. Before a cell divides, the DNA is copied, so that each of the resulting two cells will inherit the DNA sequence. Portions of a DNA molecule that specify a single functional unit are called genes; different genes have different sequences of bases. Within cells, the long strands of DNA form condensed structures called chromosomes. The specific location of a DNA sequence within a chromosome is known as a locus. If the DNA sequence at a locus varies between individuals, the different forms of this sequence are called alleles. DNA sequences can change through mutations, producing new alleles. If a mutation occurs within a gene, the new allele may affect the trait that the gene controls, altering the phenotype of the organism.[69] However, while this simple correspondence between an allele and a trait works in some cases, most traits are more complex and are controlled by quantitative trait loci (multiple interacting genes).[70][71]

Recent findings have confirmed important examples of heritable changes that cannot be explained by changes to the sequence of nucleotides in the DNA. These phenomena are classed as epigenetic inheritance systems.[72]DNA methylation marking chromatin, self-sustaining metabolic loops, gene silencing by RNA interference and the three-dimensional conformation of proteins (such as prions) are areas where epigenetic inheritance systems have been discovered at the organismic level.[73][74] Developmental biologists suggest that complex interactions in genetic networks and communication among cells can lead to heritable variations that may underlay some of the mechanics in developmental plasticity and canalisation.[75] Heritability may also occur at even larger scales. For example, ecological inheritance through the process of niche construction is defined by the regular and repeated activities of organisms in their environment. This generates a legacy of effects that modify and feed back into the selection regime of subsequent generations. Descendants inherit genes plus environmental characteristics generated by the ecological actions of ancestors.[76] Other examples of heritability in evolution that are not under the direct control of genes include the inheritance of cultural traits and symbiogenesis.[77][78]

Variation

White peppered moth
Black morph in peppered moth evolution

An individual organism's phenotype results from both its genotype and the influence from the environment it has lived in. A substantial part of the phenotypic variation in a population is caused by genotypic variation.[71] The modern evolutionary synthesis defines evolution as the change over time in this genetic variation. The frequency of one particular allele will become more or less prevalent relative to other forms of that gene. Variation disappears when a new allele reaches the point of fixation—when it either disappears from the population or replaces the ancestral allele entirely.[79]

Natural selection will only cause evolution if there is enough genetic variation in a population. Before the discovery of Mendelian genetics, one common hypothesis was blending inheritance. But with blending inheritance, genetic variance would be rapidly lost, making evolution by natural selection implausible. The Hardy–Weinberg principle provides the solution to how variation is maintained in a population with Mendelian inheritance. The frequencies of alleles (variations in a gene) will remain constant in the absence of selection, mutation, migration and genetic drift.[80]

Variation comes from mutations in the genome, reshuffling of genes through sexual reproduction and migration between populations (gene flow). Despite the constant introduction of new variation through mutation and gene flow, most of the genome of a species is identical in all individuals of that species.[81] However, even relatively small differences in genotype can lead to dramatic differences in phenotype: for example, chimpanzees and humans differ in only about 5% of their genomes.[82]

Mutation

Duplication of part of a chromosome

Mutations are changes in the DNA sequence of a cell's genome. When mutations occur, they may alter the product of a gene, or prevent the gene from functioning, or have no effect. Based on studies in the fly Drosophila melanogaster, it has been suggested that if a mutation changes a protein produced by a gene, this will probably be harmful, with about 70% of these mutations having damaging effects, and the remainder being either neutral or weakly beneficial.[83]

Mutations can involve large sections of a chromosome becoming duplicated (usually by genetic recombination), which can introduce extra copies of a gene into a genome.[84] Extra copies of genes are a major source of the raw material needed for new genes to evolve.[85] This is important because most new genes evolve within gene families from pre-existing genes that share common ancestors.[86] For example, the human eye uses four genes to make structures that sense light: three for colour vision and one for night vision; all four are descended from a single ancestral gene.[87]

New genes can be generated from an ancestral gene when a duplicate copy mutates and acquires a new function. This process is easier once a gene has been duplicated because it increases the redundancy of the system; one gene in the pair can acquire a new function while the other copy continues to perform its original function.[88][89] Other types of mutations can even generate entirely new genes from previously noncoding DNA.[90][91]

The generation of new genes can also involve small parts of several genes being duplicated, with these fragments then recombining to form new combinations with new functions.[92][93] When new genes are assembled from shuffling pre-existing parts, domains act as modules with simple independent functions, which can be mixed together to produce new combinations with new and complex functions.[94] For example, polyketide synthases are large enzymes that make antibiotics; they contain up to one hundred independent domains that each catalyse one step in the overall process, like a step in an assembly line.[95]

Sex and recombination

In asexual organisms, genes are inherited together, or linked, as they cannot mix with genes of other organisms during reproduction. In contrast, the offspring of sexual organisms contain random mixtures of their parents' chromosomes that are produced through independent assortment. In a related process called homologous recombination, sexual organisms exchange DNA between two matching chromosomes.[96] Recombination and reassortment do not alter allele frequencies, but instead change which alleles are associated with each other, producing offspring with new combinations of alleles.[97] Sex usually increases genetic variation and may increase the rate of evolution.[98][99]

This diagram illustrates the twofold cost of sex. If each individual were to contribute to the same number of offspring (two), (a) the sexual population remains the same size each generation, where the (b)Asexual reproduction population doubles in size each generation.

The two-fold cost of sex was first described by John Maynard Smith.[100] The first cost is that in sexually dimorphic species only one of the two sexes can bear young. (This cost does not apply to hermaphroditic species, like most plants and many invertebrates.) The second cost is that any individual who reproduces sexually can only pass on 50% of its genes to any individual offspring, with even less passed on as each new generation passes.[101] Yet sexual reproduction is the more common means of reproduction among eukaryotes and multicellular organisms. The Red Queen hypothesis has been used to explain the significance of sexual reproduction as a means to enable continual evolution and adaptation in response to coevolution with other species in an ever-changing environment.[101][102][103][104]

Gene flow

Gene flow is the exchange of genes between populations and between species.[105] It can therefore be a source of variation that is new to a population or to a species. Gene flow can be caused by the movement of individuals between separate populations of organisms, as might be caused by the movement of mice between inland and coastal populations, or the movement of pollen between heavy-metal-tolerant and heavy-metal-sensitive populations of grasses.

Gene transfer between species includes the formation of hybrid organisms and horizontal gene transfer. Horizontal gene transfer is the transfer of genetic material from one organism to another organism that is not its offspring; this is most common among bacteria.[106] In medicine, this contributes to the spread of antibiotic resistance, as when one bacteria acquires resistance genes it can rapidly transfer them to other species.[107] Horizontal transfer of genes from bacteria to eukaryotes such as the yeast Saccharomyces cerevisiae and the adzuki bean weevil Callosobruchus chinensis has occurred.[108][109] An example of larger-scale transfers are the eukaryotic bdelloid rotifers, which have received a range of genes from bacteria, fungi and plants.[110]Viruses can also carry DNA between organisms, allowing transfer of genes even across biological domains.[111]

Large-scale gene transfer has also occurred between the ancestors of eukaryotic cells and bacteria, during the acquisition of chloroplasts and mitochondria. It is possible that eukaryotes themselves originated from horizontal gene transfers between bacteria and archaea.[112]

Mechanisms

Mutation followed by natural selection results in a population with darker colouration.

From a neo-Darwinian perspective, evolution occurs when there are changes in the frequencies of alleles within a population of interbreeding organisms,[80] for example, the allele for black colour in a population of moths becoming more common. Mechanisms that can lead to changes in allele frequencies include natural selection, genetic drift, genetic hitchhiking, mutation and gene flow.

Natural selection

Evolution by means of natural selection is the process by which traits that enhance survival and reproduction become more common in successive generations of a population. It has often been called a 'self-evident' mechanism because it necessarily follows from three simple facts:[8]

  • Variation exists within populations of organisms with respect to morphology, physiology, and behaviour (phenotypic variation).
  • Different traits confer different rates of survival and reproduction (differential fitness).
  • These traits can be passed from generation to generation (heritability of fitness).

More offspring are produced than can possibly survive, and these conditions produce competition between organisms for survival and reproduction. Consequently, organisms with traits that give them an advantage over their competitors are more likely to pass on their traits to the next generation than those with traits that do not confer an advantage.[113] This teleonomy is the quality whereby the process of natural selection creates and preserves traits that are seemingly fitted for the functional roles they perform.[114] Consequences of selection include nonrandom mating[115] and genetic hitchhiking.

The central concept of natural selection is the evolutionary fitness of an organism.[116] Fitness is measured by an organism's ability to survive and reproduce, which determines the size of its genetic contribution to the next generation.[116] However, fitness is not the same as the total number of offspring: instead fitness is indicated by the proportion of subsequent generations that carry an organism's genes.[117] For example, if an organism could survive well and reproduce rapidly, but its offspring were all too small and weak to survive, this organism would make little genetic contribution to future generations and would thus have low fitness.[116]

If an allele increases fitness more than the other alleles of that gene, then with each generation this allele will become more common within the population. These traits are said to be 'selected for.' Examples of traits that can increase fitness are enhanced survival and increased fecundity. Conversely, the lower fitness caused by having a less beneficial or deleterious allele results in this allele becoming rarer—they are 'selected against.'[118] Importantly, the fitness of an allele is not a fixed characteristic; if the environment changes, previously neutral or harmful traits may become beneficial and previously beneficial traits become harmful.[69] However, even if the direction of selection does reverse in this way, traits that were lost in the past may not re-evolve in an identical form (see Dollo's law).[119][120] However, a re-activation of dormant genes, as long as they have not been eliminated from the genome and were only suppressed perhaps for hundreds of generations, can lead to the re-occurrence of traits thought to be lost like hindlegs in dolphins, teeth in chickens, wings in wingless stick insects, tails and additional nipples in humans etc.[121] 'Throwbacks' such as these are known as atavisms.

These charts depict the different types of genetic selection. On each graph, the x-axis variable is the type of phenotypic trait and the y-axis variable is the number of organisms. Group A is the original population and Group B is the population after selection.
· Graph 1 shows directional selection, in which a single extreme phenotype is favoured.
· Graph 2 depicts stabilizing selection, where the intermediate phenotype is favoured over the extreme traits.
· Graph 3 shows disruptive selection, in which the extreme phenotypes are favoured over the intermediate.

Natural selection within a population for a trait that can vary across a range of values, such as height, can be categorised into three different types. The first is directional selection, which is a shift in the average value of a trait over time—for example, organisms slowly getting taller.[122] Secondly, disruptive selection is selection for extreme trait values and often results in two different values becoming most common, with selection against the average value. This would be when either short or tall organisms had an advantage, but not those of medium height. Finally, in stabilising selection there is selection against extreme trait values on both ends, which causes a decrease in variance around the average value and less diversity.[113][123] This would, for example, cause organisms to eventually have a similar height.

A special case of natural selection is sexual selection, which is selection for any trait that increases mating success by increasing the attractiveness of an organism to potential mates.[124] Traits that evolved through sexual selection are particularly prominent among males of several animal species. Although sexually favoured, traits such as cumbersome antlers, mating calls, large body size and bright colours often attract predation, which compromises the survival of individual males.[125][126] This survival disadvantage is balanced by higher reproductive success in males that show these hard-to-fake, sexually selected traits.[127]

Natural selection most generally makes nature the measure against which individuals and individual traits, are more or less likely to survive. 'Nature' in this sense refers to an ecosystem, that is, a system in which organisms interact with every other element, physical as well as biological, in their local environment. Eugene Odum, a founder of ecology, defined an ecosystem as: 'Any unit that includes all of the organisms...in a given area interacting with the physical environment so that a flow of energy leads to clearly defined trophic structure, biotic diversity, and material cycles (i.e., exchange of materials between living and nonliving parts) within the system....'[128] Each population within an ecosystem occupies a distinct niche, or position, with distinct relationships to other parts of the system. These relationships involve the life history of the organism, its position in the food chain and its geographic range. This broad understanding of nature enables scientists to delineate specific forces which, together, comprise natural selection.

Natural selection can act at different levels of organisation, such as genes, cells, individual organisms, groups of organisms and species.[129][130][131] Selection can act at multiple levels simultaneously.[132] An example of selection occurring below the level of the individual organism are genes called transposons, which can replicate and spread throughout a genome.[133] Selection at a level above the individual, such as group selection, may allow the evolution of cooperation, as discussed below.[134]

Biased mutation

In addition to being a major source of variation, mutation may also function as a mechanism of evolution when there are different probabilities at the molecular level for different mutations to occur, a process known as mutation bias.[135] If two genotypes, for example one with the nucleotide G and another with the nucleotide A in the same position, have the same fitness, but mutation from G to A happens more often than mutation from A to G, then genotypes with A will tend to evolve.[136] Different insertion vs. deletion mutation biases in different taxa can lead to the evolution of different genome sizes.[137][138] Developmental or mutational biases have also been observed in morphological evolution.[139][140] For example, according to the phenotype-first theory of evolution, mutations can eventually cause the genetic assimilation of traits that were previously induced by the environment.[141][142][143]

Mutation bias effects are superimposed on other processes. If selection would favour either one out of two mutations, but there is no extra advantage to having both, then the mutation that occurs the most frequently is the one that is most likely to become fixed in a population.[144][145] Mutations leading to the loss of function of a gene are much more common than mutations that produce a new, fully functional gene. Most loss of function mutations are selected against. But when selection is weak, mutation bias towards loss of function can affect evolution.[146] For example, pigments are no longer useful when animals live in the darkness of caves, and tend to be lost.[147] This kind of loss of function can occur because of mutation bias, and/or because the function had a cost, and once the benefit of the function disappeared, natural selection leads to the loss. Loss of sporulation ability in Bacillus subtilis during laboratory evolution appears to have been caused by mutation bias, rather than natural selection against the cost of maintaining sporulation ability.[148] When there is no selection for loss of function, the speed at which loss evolves depends more on the mutation rate than it does on the effective population size,[149] indicating that it is driven more by mutation bias than by genetic drift. In parasitic organisms, mutation bias leads to selection pressures as seen in Ehrlichia. Mutations are biased towards antigenic variants in outer-membrane proteins.

Genetic drift

Simulation of genetic drift of 20 unlinked alleles in populations of 10 (top) and 100 (bottom). Drift to fixation is more rapid in the smaller population.

Genetic drift is the random fluctuations of allele frequencies within a population from one generation to the next.[150] When selective forces are absent or relatively weak, allele frequencies are equally likely to drift upward or downward at each successive generation because the alleles are subject to sampling error.[151] This drift halts when an allele eventually becomes fixed, either by disappearing from the population or replacing the other alleles entirely. Genetic drift may therefore eliminate some alleles from a population due to chance alone. Even in the absence of selective forces, genetic drift can cause two separate populations that began with the same genetic structure to drift apart into two divergent populations with different sets of alleles.[152]

The neutral theory of molecular evolution proposed that most evolutionary changes are the result of the fixation of neutral mutations by genetic drift.[153] Hence, in this model, most genetic changes in a population are the result of constant mutation pressure and genetic drift.[154] This form of the neutral theory is now largely abandoned, since it does not seem to fit the genetic variation seen in nature.[155][156] However, a more recent and better-supported version of this model is the nearly neutral theory, where a mutation that would be effectively neutral in a small population is not necessarily neutral in a large population.[113] Other alternative theories propose that genetic drift is dwarfed by other stochastic forces in evolution, such as genetic hitchhiking, also known as genetic draft.[151][157][158]

The time for a neutral allele to become fixed by genetic drift depends on population size, with fixation occurring more rapidly in smaller populations.[159] The number of individuals in a population is not critical, but instead a measure known as the effective population size.[160] The effective population is usually smaller than the total population since it takes into account factors such as the level of inbreeding and the stage of the lifecycle in which the population is the smallest.[160] The effective population size may not be the same for every gene in the same population.[161]

It is usually difficult to measure the relative importance of selection and neutral processes, including drift.[162] The comparative importance of adaptive and non-adaptive forces in driving evolutionary change is an area of current research.[163]

Genetic hitchhiking

Recombination allows alleles on the same strand of DNA to become separated. However, the rate of recombination is low (approximately two events per chromosome per generation). As a result, genes close together on a chromosome may not always be shuffled away from each other and genes that are close together tend to be inherited together, a phenomenon known as linkage.[164] This tendency is measured by finding how often two alleles occur together on a single chromosome compared to expectations, which is called their linkage disequilibrium. A set of alleles that is usually inherited in a group is called a haplotype. This can be important when one allele in a particular haplotype is strongly beneficial: natural selection can drive a selective sweep that will also cause the other alleles in the haplotype to become more common in the population; this effect is called genetic hitchhiking or genetic draft.[165] Genetic draft caused by the fact that some neutral genes are genetically linked to others that are under selection can be partially captured by an appropriate effective population size.[157]

Gene flow

Gene flow involves the exchange of genes between populations and between species.[105] The presence or absence of gene flow fundamentally changes the course of evolution. Due to the complexity of organisms, any two completely isolated populations will eventually evolve genetic incompatibilities through neutral processes, as in the Bateson-Dobzhansky-Muller model, even if both populations remain essentially identical in terms of their adaptation to the environment.

If genetic differentiation between populations develops, gene flow between populations can introduce traits or alleles which are disadvantageous in the local population and this may lead to organisms within these populations evolving mechanisms that prevent mating with genetically distant populations, eventually resulting in the appearance of new species. Thus, exchange of genetic information between individuals is fundamentally important for the development of the Biological Species Concept (BSC).

During the development of the modern synthesis, Sewall Wright developed his shifting balance theory, which regarded gene flow between partially isolated populations as an important aspect of adaptive evolution.[166] However, recently there has been substantial criticism of the importance of the shifting balance theory.[167]

Outcomes

A visual demonstration of rapid antibiotic resistance evolution by E. coli growing across a plate with increasing concentrations of trimethoprim.[168]

Evolution influences every aspect of the form and behaviour of organisms. Most prominent are the specific behavioural and physical adaptations that are the outcome of natural selection. These adaptations increase fitness by aiding activities such as finding food, avoiding predators or attracting mates. Organisms can also respond to selection by cooperating with each other, usually by aiding their relatives or engaging in mutually beneficial symbiosis. In the longer term, evolution produces new species through splitting ancestral populations of organisms into new groups that cannot or will not interbreed.

These outcomes of evolution are distinguished based on time scale as macroevolution versus microevolution. Macroevolution refers to evolution that occurs at or above the level of species, in particular speciation and extinction; whereas microevolution refers to smaller evolutionary changes within a species or population, in particular shifts in allele frequency and adaptation.[169] In general, macroevolution is regarded as the outcome of long periods of microevolution.[170] Thus, the distinction between micro- and macroevolution is not a fundamental one—the difference is simply the time involved.[171] However, in macroevolution, the traits of the entire species may be important. For instance, a large amount of variation among individuals allows a species to rapidly adapt to new habitats, lessening the chance of it going extinct, while a wide geographic range increases the chance of speciation, by making it more likely that part of the population will become isolated. In this sense, microevolution and macroevolution might involve selection at different levels—with microevolution acting on genes and organisms, versus macroevolutionary processes such as species selection acting on entire species and affecting their rates of speciation and extinction.[172][173][174]

A common misconception is that evolution has goals, long-term plans, or an innate tendency for 'progress', as expressed in beliefs such as orthogenesis and evolutionism; realistically however, evolution has no long-term goal and does not necessarily produce greater complexity.[175][176][177] Although complex species have evolved, they occur as a side effect of the overall number of organisms increasing and simple forms of life still remain more common in the biosphere.[178] For example, the overwhelming majority of species are microscopic prokaryotes, which form about half the world's biomass despite their small size,[179] and constitute the vast majority of Earth's biodiversity.[180] Simple organisms have therefore been the dominant form of life on Earth throughout its history and continue to be the main form of life up to the present day, with complex life only appearing more diverse because it is more noticeable.[181] Indeed, the evolution of microorganisms is particularly important to modern evolutionary research, since their rapid reproduction allows the study of experimental evolution and the observation of evolution and adaptation in real time.[182][183]

Adaptation

Homologous bones in the limbs of tetrapods. The bones of these animals have the same basic structure, but have been adapted for specific uses.

Adaptation is the process that makes organisms better suited to their habitat.[184][185] Also, the term adaptation may refer to a trait that is important for an organism's survival. For example, the adaptation of horses' teeth to the grinding of grass. By using the term adaptation for the evolutionary process and adaptive trait for the product (the bodily part or function), the two senses of the word may be distinguished. Adaptations are produced by natural selection.[186] The following definitions are due to Theodosius Dobzhansky:

  1. Adaptation is the evolutionary process whereby an organism becomes better able to live in its habitat or habitats.[187]
  2. Adaptedness is the state of being adapted: the degree to which an organism is able to live and reproduce in a given set of habitats.[188]
  3. An adaptive trait is an aspect of the developmental pattern of the organism which enables or enhances the probability of that organism surviving and reproducing.[189]

Adaptation may cause either the gain of a new feature, or the loss of an ancestral feature. An example that shows both types of change is bacterial adaptation to antibiotic selection, with genetic changes causing antibiotic resistance by both modifying the target of the drug, or increasing the activity of transporters that pump the drug out of the cell.[190] Other striking examples are the bacteria Escherichia coli evolving the ability to use citric acid as a nutrient in a long-term laboratory experiment,[191]Flavobacterium evolving a novel enzyme that allows these bacteria to grow on the by-products of nylon manufacturing,[192][193] and the soil bacterium Sphingobium evolving an entirely new metabolic pathway that degrades the synthetic pesticidepentachlorophenol.[194][195] An interesting but still controversial idea is that some adaptations might increase the ability of organisms to generate genetic diversity and adapt by natural selection (increasing organisms' evolvability).[196][197][198][199][200]

A baleen whale skeleton, a and b label flipper bones, which were adapted from front leg bones: while c indicates vestigial leg bones, suggesting an adaptation from land to sea.[201]

Adaptation occurs through the gradual modification of existing structures. Consequently, structures with similar internal organisation may have different functions in related organisms. This is the result of a single ancestral structure being adapted to function in different ways. The bones within bat wings, for example, are very similar to those in mice feet and primate hands, due to the descent of all these structures from a common mammalian ancestor.[202] However, since all living organisms are related to some extent,[203] even organs that appear to have little or no structural similarity, such as arthropod, squid and vertebrate eyes, or the limbs and wings of arthropods and vertebrates, can depend on a common set of homologous genes that control their assembly and function; this is called deep homology.[204][205]

During evolution, some structures may lose their original function and become vestigial structures.[206] Such structures may have little or no function in a current species, yet have a clear function in ancestral species, or other closely related species. Examples include pseudogenes,[207] the non-functional remains of eyes in blind cave-dwelling fish,[208] wings in flightless birds,[209] the presence of hip bones in whales and snakes,[201] and sexual traits in organisms that reproduce via asexual reproduction.[210] Examples of vestigial structures in humans include wisdom teeth,[211] the coccyx,[206] the vermiform appendix,[206] and other behavioural vestiges such as goose bumps[212][213] and primitive reflexes.[214][215][216]

However, many traits that appear to be simple adaptations are in fact exaptations: structures originally adapted for one function, but which coincidentally became somewhat useful for some other function in the process.[217] One example is the African lizard Holaspis guentheri, which developed an extremely flat head for hiding in crevices, as can be seen by looking at its near relatives. However, in this species, the head has become so flattened that it assists in gliding from tree to tree—an exaptation.[217] Within cells, molecular machines such as the bacterial flagella[218] and protein sorting machinery[219] evolved by the recruitment of several pre-existing proteins that previously had different functions.[169] Another example is the recruitment of enzymes from glycolysis and xenobiotic metabolism to serve as structural proteins called crystallins within the lenses of organisms' eyes.[220][221]

An area of current investigation in evolutionary developmental biology is the developmental basis of adaptations and exaptations.[222] This research addresses the origin and evolution of embryonic development and how modifications of development and developmental processes produce novel features.[223] These studies have shown that evolution can alter development to produce new structures, such as embryonic bone structures that develop into the jaw in other animals instead forming part of the middle ear in mammals.[224] It is also possible for structures that have been lost in evolution to reappear due to changes in developmental genes, such as a mutation in chickens causing embryos to grow teeth similar to those of crocodiles.[225] It is now becoming clear that most alterations in the form of organisms are due to changes in a small set of conserved genes.[226]

Coevolution

Biology
Common garter snake (Thamnophis sirtalis sirtalis) has evolved resistance to the defensive substancetetrodotoxin in its amphibian prey.

Interactions between organisms can produce both conflict and cooperation. When the interaction is between pairs of species, such as a pathogen and a host, or a predator and its prey, these species can develop matched sets of adaptations. Here, the evolution of one species causes adaptations in a second species. These changes in the second species then, in turn, cause new adaptations in the first species. This cycle of selection and response is called coevolution.[227] An example is the production of tetrodotoxin in the rough-skinned newt and the evolution of tetrodotoxin resistance in its predator, the common garter snake. In this predator-prey pair, an evolutionary arms race has produced high levels of toxin in the newt and correspondingly high levels of toxin resistance in the snake.[228]

Cooperation

Not all co-evolved interactions between species involve conflict.[229] Many cases of mutually beneficial interactions have evolved. For instance, an extreme cooperation exists between plants and the mycorrhizal fungi that grow on their roots and aid the plant in absorbing nutrients from the soil.[230] This is a reciprocal relationship as the plants provide the fungi with sugars from photosynthesis. Here, the fungi actually grow inside plant cells, allowing them to exchange nutrients with their hosts, while sending signals that suppress the plant immune system.[231]

Coalitions between organisms of the same species have also evolved. An extreme case is the eusociality found in social insects, such as bees, termites and ants, where sterile insects feed and guard the small number of organisms in a colony that are able to reproduce. On an even smaller scale, the somatic cells that make up the body of an animal limit their reproduction so they can maintain a stable organism, which then supports a small number of the animal's germ cells to produce offspring. Here, somatic cells respond to specific signals that instruct them whether to grow, remain as they are, or die. If cells ignore these signals and multiply inappropriately, their uncontrolled growth causes cancer.[232]

Such cooperation within species may have evolved through the process of kin selection, which is where one organism acts to help raise a relative's offspring.[233] This activity is selected for because if the helping individual contains alleles which promote the helping activity, it is likely that its kin will also contain these alleles and thus those alleles will be passed on.[234] Other processes that may promote cooperation include group selection, where cooperation provides benefits to a group of organisms.[235]

Speciation

The four geographic modes of speciation

Speciation is the process where a species diverges into two or more descendant species.[236]

There are multiple ways to define the concept of 'species.' The choice of definition is dependent on the particularities of the species concerned.[237] For example, some species concepts apply more readily toward sexually reproducing organisms while others lend themselves better toward asexual organisms. Despite the diversity of various species concepts, these various concepts can be placed into one of three broad philosophical approaches: interbreeding, ecological and phylogenetic.[238] The Biological Species Concept (BSC) is a classic example of the interbreeding approach. Defined by evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr in 1942, the BSC states that 'species are groups of actually or potentially interbreeding natural populations, which are reproductively isolated from other such groups.'[239] Despite its wide and long-term use, the BSC like others is not without controversy, for example because these concepts cannot be applied to prokaryotes,[240] and this is called the species problem.[237] Some researchers have attempted a unifying monistic definition of species, while others adopt a pluralistic approach and suggest that there may be different ways to logically interpret the definition of a species.[237][238]

Barriers to reproduction between two diverging sexual populations are required for the populations to become new species. Gene flow may slow this process by spreading the new genetic variants also to the other populations. Depending on how far two species have diverged since their most recent common ancestor, it may still be possible for them to produce offspring, as with horses and donkeys mating to produce mules.[241] Such hybrids are generally infertile. In this case, closely related species may regularly interbreed, but hybrids will be selected against and the species will remain distinct. However, viable hybrids are occasionally formed and these new species can either have properties intermediate between their parent species, or possess a totally new phenotype.[242] The importance of hybridisation in producing new species of animals is unclear, although cases have been seen in many types of animals,[243] with the gray tree frog being a particularly well-studied example.[244]

Speciation has been observed multiple times under both controlled laboratory conditions (see laboratory experiments of speciation) and in nature.[245] In sexually reproducing organisms, speciation results from reproductive isolation followed by genealogical divergence. There are four primary geographic modes of speciation. The most common in animals is allopatric speciation, which occurs in populations initially isolated geographically, such as by habitat fragmentation or migration. Selection under these conditions can produce very rapid changes in the appearance and behaviour of organisms.[246][247] As selection and drift act independently on populations isolated from the rest of their species, separation may eventually produce organisms that cannot interbreed.[248]

The second mode of speciation is peripatric speciation, which occurs when small populations of organisms become isolated in a new environment. This differs from allopatric speciation in that the isolated populations are numerically much smaller than the parental population. Here, the founder effect causes rapid speciation after an increase in inbreeding increases selection on homozygotes, leading to rapid genetic change.[249]

The third mode is parapatric speciation. This is similar to peripatric speciation in that a small population enters a new habitat, but differs in that there is no physical separation between these two populations. Instead, speciation results from the evolution of mechanisms that reduce gene flow between the two populations.[236] Generally this occurs when there has been a drastic change in the environment within the parental species' habitat. One example is the grass Anthoxanthum odoratum, which can undergo parapatric speciation in response to localised metal pollution from mines.[250] Here, plants evolve that have resistance to high levels of metals in the soil. Selection against interbreeding with the metal-sensitive parental population produced a gradual change in the flowering time of the metal-resistant plants, which eventually produced complete reproductive isolation. Selection against hybrids between the two populations may cause reinforcement, which is the evolution of traits that promote mating within a species, as well as character displacement, which is when two species become more distinct in appearance.[251]

Geographical isolation of finches on the Galápagos Islands produced over a dozen new species.
Mader 10th edition biology pdf

Finally, in sympatric speciation species diverge without geographic isolation or changes in habitat. This form is rare since even a small amount of gene flow may remove genetic differences between parts of a population.[252] Generally, sympatric speciation in animals requires the evolution of both genetic differences and nonrandom mating, to allow reproductive isolation to evolve.[253]

One type of sympatric speciation involves crossbreeding of two related species to produce a new hybrid species. This is not common in animals as animal hybrids are usually sterile. This is because during meiosis the homologous chromosomes from each parent are from different species and cannot successfully pair. However, it is more common in plants because plants often double their number of chromosomes, to form polyploids.[254] This allows the chromosomes from each parental species to form matching pairs during meiosis, since each parent's chromosomes are represented by a pair already.[255] An example of such a speciation event is when the plant species Arabidopsis thaliana and Arabidopsis arenosa crossbred to give the new species Arabidopsis suecica.[256] This happened about 20,000 years ago,[257] and the speciation process has been repeated in the laboratory, which allows the study of the genetic mechanisms involved in this process.[258] Indeed, chromosome doubling within a species may be a common cause of reproductive isolation, as half the doubled chromosomes will be unmatched when breeding with undoubled organisms.[259]

Speciation events are important in the theory of punctuated equilibrium, which accounts for the pattern in the fossil record of short 'bursts' of evolution interspersed with relatively long periods of stasis, where species remain relatively unchanged.[260] In this theory, speciation and rapid evolution are linked, with natural selection and genetic drift acting most strongly on organisms undergoing speciation in novel habitats or small populations. As a result, the periods of stasis in the fossil record correspond to the parental population and the organisms undergoing speciation and rapid evolution are found in small populations or geographically restricted habitats and therefore rarely being preserved as fossils.[173]

Extinction

Tyrannosaurus rex. Non-aviandinosaurs died out in the Cretaceous–Paleogene extinction event at the end of the Cretaceous period.

Extinction is the disappearance of an entire species. Extinction is not an unusual event, as species regularly appear through speciation and disappear through extinction.[261] Nearly all animal and plant species that have lived on Earth are now extinct,[262] and extinction appears to be the ultimate fate of all species.[263] These extinctions have happened continuously throughout the history of life, although the rate of extinction spikes in occasional mass extinction events.[264] The Cretaceous–Paleogene extinction event, during which the non-avian dinosaurs became extinct, is the most well-known, but the earlier Permian–Triassic extinction event was even more severe, with approximately 96% of all marine species driven to extinction.[264] The Holocene extinction event is an ongoing mass extinction associated with humanity's expansion across the globe over the past few thousand years. Present-day extinction rates are 100–1000 times greater than the background rate and up to 30% of current species may be extinct by the mid 21st century.[265] Human activities are now the primary cause of the ongoing extinction event;[266]global warming may further accelerate it in the future.[267] Despite the estimated extinction of more than 99 percent of all species that ever lived on Earth,[268][269] about 1 trillion species are estimated to be on Earth currently with only one-thousandth of one percent described.[270]

The role of extinction in evolution is not very well understood and may depend on which type of extinction is considered.[264] The causes of the continuous 'low-level' extinction events, which form the majority of extinctions, may be the result of competition between species for limited resources (the competitive exclusion principle).[60] If one species can out-compete another, this could produce species selection, with the fitter species surviving and the other species being driven to extinction.[130] The intermittent mass extinctions are also important, but instead of acting as a selective force, they drastically reduce diversity in a nonspecific manner and promote bursts of rapid evolution and speciation in survivors.[271]

Evolutionary history of life

Origin of life

The Earth is about 4.54 billion years old.[272][273][274] The earliest undisputed evidence of life on Earth dates from at least 3.5 billion years ago,[13][275] during the Eoarchean Era after a geological crust started to solidify following the earlier molten Hadean Eon. Microbial mat fossils have been found in 3.48 billion-year-old sandstone in Western Australia.[15][16][17] Other early physical evidence of a biogenic substance is graphite in 3.7 billion-year-old metasedimentary rocks discovered in Western Greenland[14] as well as 'remains of biotic life' found in 4.1 billion-year-old rocks in Western Australia.[276][277] Commenting on the Australian findings, Stephen Blair Hedges wrote, 'If life arose relatively quickly on Earth, then it could be common in the universe.'[276][278] In July 2016, scientists reported identifying a set of 355 genes from the last universal common ancestor (LUCA) of all organisms living on Earth.[279]

More than 99 percent of all species, amounting to over five billion species,[280] that ever lived on Earth are estimated to be extinct.[268][269] Estimates on the number of Earth's current species range from 10 million to 14 million,[281][282] of which about 1.9 million are estimated to have been named[283] and 1.6 million documented in a central database to date,[284] leaving at least 80 percent not yet described.

Highly energetic chemistry is thought to have produced a self-replicating molecule around 4 billion years ago, and half a billion years later the last common ancestor of all life existed.[11] The current scientific consensus is that the complex biochemistry that makes up life came from simpler chemical reactions.[285] The beginning of life may have included self-replicating molecules such as RNA[286] and the assembly of simple cells.[287]

Common descent

All organisms on Earth are descended from a common ancestor or ancestral gene pool.[203][288] Current species are a stage in the process of evolution, with their diversity the product of a long series of speciation and extinction events.[289] The common descent of organisms was first deduced from four simple facts about organisms: First, they have geographic distributions that cannot be explained by local adaptation. Second, the diversity of life is not a set of completely unique organisms, but organisms that share morphological similarities. Third, vestigial traits with no clear purpose resemble functional ancestral traits. Fourth, organisms can be classified using these similarities into a hierarchy of nested groups, similar to a family tree.[290]

The hominoids are descendants of a common ancestor.

Modern research has suggested that, due to horizontal gene transfer, this 'tree of life' may be more complicated than a simple branching tree since some genes have spread independently between distantly related species.[291][292] To solve this problem and others, some authors prefer to use the 'Coral of life' as a metaphor or a mathematical model to illustrate the evolution of life. This view dates back to an idea briefly mentioned by Darwin but later abandoned.[293]

Past species have also left records of their evolutionary history. Fossils, along with the comparative anatomy of present-day organisms, constitute the morphological, or anatomical, record.[294] By comparing the anatomies of both modern and extinct species, paleontologists can infer the lineages of those species. However, this approach is most successful for organisms that had hard body parts, such as shells, bones or teeth. Further, as prokaryotes such as bacteria and archaea share a limited set of common morphologies, their fossils do not provide information on their ancestry.

More recently, evidence for common descent has come from the study of biochemical similarities between organisms. For example, all living cells use the same basic set of nucleotides and amino acids.[295] The development of molecular genetics has revealed the record of evolution left in organisms' genomes: dating when species diverged through the molecular clock produced by mutations.[296] For example, these DNA sequence comparisons have revealed that humans and chimpanzees share 98% of their genomes and analysing the few areas where they differ helps shed light on when the common ancestor of these species existed.[297]

Evolution of life

Evolutionary tree showing the divergence of modern species from their common ancestor in the centre.[298] The three domains are coloured, with bacteria blue, archaea green and eukaryotes red.

Prokaryotes inhabited the Earth from approximately 3–4 billion years ago.[299][300] No obvious changes in morphology or cellular organisation occurred in these organisms over the next few billion years.[301] The eukaryotic cells emerged between 1.6–2.7 billion years ago. The next major change in cell structure came when bacteria were engulfed by eukaryotic cells, in a cooperative association called endosymbiosis.[302][303] The engulfed bacteria and the host cell then underwent coevolution, with the bacteria evolving into either mitochondria or hydrogenosomes.[304] Another engulfment of cyanobacterial-like organisms led to the formation of chloroplasts in algae and plants.[305]

The history of life was that of the unicellular eukaryotes, prokaryotes and archaea until about 610 million years ago when multicellular organisms began to appear in the oceans in the Ediacaran period.[299][306] The evolution of multicellularity occurred in multiple independent events, in organisms as diverse as sponges, brown algae, cyanobacteria, slime moulds and myxobacteria.[307] In January 2016, scientists reported that, about 800 million years ago, a minor genetic change in a single molecule called GK-PID may have allowed organisms to go from a single cell organism to one of many cells.[308]

Soon after the emergence of these first multicellular organisms, a remarkable amount of biological diversity appeared over approximately 10 million years, in an event called the Cambrian explosion. Here, the majority of types of modern animals appeared in the fossil record, as well as unique lineages that subsequently became extinct.[309] Various triggers for the Cambrian explosion have been proposed, including the accumulation of oxygen in the atmosphere from photosynthesis.[310]

About 500 million years ago, plants and fungi colonised the land and were soon followed by arthropods and other animals.[311] Insects were particularly successful and even today make up the majority of animal species.[312]Amphibians first appeared around 364 million years ago, followed by early amniotes and birds around 155 million years ago (both from 'reptile'-like lineages), mammals around 129 million years ago, homininae around 10 million years ago and modern humans around 250,000 years ago.[313][314][315] However, despite the evolution of these large animals, smaller organisms similar to the types that evolved early in this process continue to be highly successful and dominate the Earth, with the majority of both biomass and species being prokaryotes.[180]

Applications

Concepts and models used in evolutionary biology, such as natural selection, have many applications.[316]

Artificial selection is the intentional selection of traits in a population of organisms. This has been used for thousands of years in the domestication of plants and animals.[317] More recently, such selection has become a vital part of genetic engineering, with selectable markers such as antibiotic resistance genes being used to manipulate DNA. Proteins with valuable properties have evolved by repeated rounds of mutation and selection (for example modified enzymes and new antibodies) in a process called directed evolution.[318]

Understanding the changes that have occurred during an organism's evolution can reveal the genes needed to construct parts of the body, genes which may be involved in human genetic disorders.[319] For example, the Mexican tetra is an albino cavefish that lost its eyesight during evolution. Breeding together different populations of this blind fish produced some offspring with functional eyes, since different mutations had occurred in the isolated populations that had evolved in different caves.[320] This helped identify genes required for vision and pigmentation.[321]

Evolutionary theory has many applications in medicine. Many human diseases are not static phenomena, but capable of evolution. Viruses, bacteria, fungi and cancers evolve to be resistant to host immune defences, as well as pharmaceutical drugs.[322][323][324] These same problems occur in agriculture with pesticide[325] and herbicide[326] resistance. It is possible that we are facing the end of the effective life of most of available antibiotics[327] and predicting the evolution and evolvability[328] of our pathogens and devising strategies to slow or circumvent it is requiring deeper knowledge of the complex forces driving evolution at the molecular level.[329]

In computer science, simulations of evolution using evolutionary algorithms and artificial life started in the 1960s and were extended with simulation of artificial selection.[330] Artificial evolution became a widely recognised optimisation method as a result of the work of Ingo Rechenberg in the 1960s. He used evolution strategies to solve complex engineering problems.[331]Genetic algorithms in particular became popular through the writing of John Henry Holland.[332] Practical applications also include automatic evolution of computer programmes.[333] Evolutionary algorithms are now used to solve multi-dimensional problems more efficiently than software produced by human designers and also to optimise the design of systems.[334]

Social and cultural responses

As evolution became widely accepted in the 1870s, caricatures of Charles Darwin with an ape or monkey body symbolised evolution.[335]

In the 19th century, particularly after the publication of On the Origin of Species in 1859, the idea that life had evolved was an active source of academic debate centred on the philosophical, social and religious implications of evolution. Today, the modern evolutionary synthesis is accepted by a vast majority of scientists.[60] However, evolution remains a contentious concept for some theists.[336]

While various religions and denominations have reconciled their beliefs with evolution through concepts such as theistic evolution, there are creationists who believe that evolution is contradicted by the creation myths found in their religions and who raise various objections to evolution.[169][337][338] As had been demonstrated by responses to the publication of Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation in 1844, the most controversial aspect of evolutionary biology is the implication of human evolution that humans share common ancestry with apes and that the mental and moral faculties of humanity have the same types of natural causes as other inherited traits in animals.[339] In some countries, notably the United States, these tensions between science and religion have fuelled the current creation–evolution controversy, a religious conflict focusing on politics and public education.[340] While other scientific fields such as cosmology[341] and Earth science[342] also conflict with literal interpretations of many religious texts, evolutionary biology experiences significantly more opposition from religious literalists.

The teaching of evolution in American secondary school biology classes was uncommon in most of the first half of the 20th century. The Scopes Trial decision of 1925 caused the subject to become very rare in American secondary biology textbooks for a generation, but it was gradually re-introduced later and became legally protected with the 1968 Epperson v. Arkansas decision. Since then, the competing religious belief of creationism was legally disallowed in secondary school curricula in various decisions in the 1970s and 1980s, but it returned in pseudoscientific form as intelligent design (ID), to be excluded once again in the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District case.[343] The debate over Darwin's ideas did not generate significant controversy in China. [344]

See also

References

  1. ^Hall & Hallgrímsson 2008, pp. 4–6
  2. ^'Evolution Resources'. Washington, DC: National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. 2016. Archived from the original on 2016-06-03.
  3. ^Futuyma, Douglas J.; Kirkpatrick, Mark (2017). 'Mutation and variation'. Evolution (Fourth ed.). Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates, Inc. pp. 79–102. ISBN978-1-60535-605-1.
  4. ^Scott-Phillips, Thomas C.; Laland, Kevin N.; Shuker, David M.; Dickins, Thomas E.; West, Stuart A. (May 2014). 'The Niche Construction Perspective: A Critical Appraisal'. Evolution. 68 (5): 1231–1243. doi:10.1111/evo.12332. ISSN0014-3820. PMC4261998. PMID24325256. Evolutionary processes are generally thought of as processes by which these changes occur. Four such processes are widely recognized: natural selection (in the broad sense, to include sexual selection), genetic drift, mutation, and migration (Fisher 1930; Haldane 1932). The latter two generate variation; the first two sort it.
  5. ^Hall & Hallgrímsson 2008, pp. 3–5
  6. ^Voet, Donald; Voet, Judith G.; Pratt, Charlotte W. (2016). 'Introduction to the chemistry of life'. Fundamentals of Biochemistry: Life at the molecular level (Fifth ed.). Hoboken, New Jersey: Wiley. pp. 1–22. ISBN978-1-11-891840-1.
  7. ^Darwin, Charles (1860). On the Origin of Species (2nd ed.). London: John Murray. p. 490.
  8. ^ abLewontin, Richard C. (November 1970). 'The Units of Selection'(PDF). Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics. 1: 1–18. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.01.110170.000245. ISSN1545-2069. JSTOR2096764. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2015-02-06.
  9. ^Futuyma, Douglas J.; Kirkpatrick, Mark (2017). 'Evolutionary Biology'. Evolution (Fourth ed.). Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates, Inc. pp. 3–26. ISBN978-1-60535-605-1.
  10. ^Kampourakis 2014, pp. 127–129
  11. ^ abDoolittle, W. Ford (February 2000). 'Uprooting the Tree of Life'(PDF). Scientific American. 282 (2): 90–95. Bibcode:2000SciAm.282b..90D. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0200-90. ISSN0036-8733. PMID10710791. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2006-09-07. Retrieved 2015-04-05.
  12. ^Glansdorff, Nicolas; Ying Xu; Labedan, Bernard (July 9, 2008). 'The Last Universal Common Ancestor: emergence, constitution and genetic legacy of an elusive forerunner'. Biology Direct. 3: 29. doi:10.1186/1745-6150-3-29. ISSN1745-6150. PMC2478661. PMID18613974.
  13. ^ abSchopf, J. William; Kudryavtsev, Anatoliy B.; Czaja, Andrew D.; Tripathi, Abhishek B. (October 5, 2007). 'Evidence of Archean life: Stromatolites and microfossils'. Precambrian Research. 158 (3–4): 141–155. Bibcode:2007PreR..158..141S. doi:10.1016/j.precamres.2007.04.009. ISSN0301-9268.
  14. ^ abOhtomo, Yoko; Kakegawa, Takeshi; Ishida, Akizumi; et al. (January 2014). 'Evidence for biogenic graphite in early Archaean Isua metasedimentary rocks'. Nature Geoscience. 7 (1): 25–28. Bibcode:2014NatGe...7...25O. doi:10.1038/ngeo2025. ISSN1752-0894.
  15. ^ abBorenstein, Seth (November 13, 2013). 'Oldest fossil found: Meet your microbial mom'. Excite. Yonkers, New York: Mindspark Interactive Network. Associated Press. Archived from the original on June 29, 2015. Retrieved 2015-05-31.
  16. ^ abPearlman, Jonathan (November 13, 2013). ''Oldest signs of life on Earth found''. The Daily Telegraph. London: Telegraph Media Group. Archived from the original on 2014-12-16. Retrieved 2014-12-15.
  17. ^ abNoffke, Nora; Christian, Daniel; Wacey, David; Hazen, Robert M. (November 16, 2013). 'Microbially Induced Sedimentary Structures Recording an Ancient Ecosystem in the ca. 3.48 Billion-Year-Old Dresser Formation, Pilbara, Western Australia'. Astrobiology. 13 (12): 1103–1124. Bibcode:2013AsBio..13.1103N. doi:10.1089/ast.2013.1030. ISSN1531-1074. PMC3870916. PMID24205812.
  18. ^Futuyma 2004, p. 33
  19. ^Panno 2005, pp. xv-16
  20. ^NAS 2008, p. 17Archived 2015-06-30 at the Wayback Machine
  21. ^Futuyma, Douglas J., ed. (1999). 'Evolution, Science, and Society: Evolutionary Biology and the National Research Agenda'(PDF) (Executive summary). New Brunswick, New Jersey: Office of University Publications, Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey. OCLC43422991. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2012-01-31. Retrieved 2014-11-24.
  22. ^Darwin 1909, p. 53
  23. ^Kirk, Raven & Schofield 1983, pp. 100–142, 280–321
  24. ^Lucretius
  25. ^Sedley, David (2003). 'Lucretius and the New Empedocles'(PDF). Leeds International Classical Studies. 2 (4). ISSN1477-3643. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-11-25.
  26. ^Torrey, Harry Beal; Felin, Frances (March 1937). 'Was Aristotle an Evolutionist?'. The Quarterly Review of Biology. 12 (1): 1–18. doi:10.1086/394520. ISSN0033-5770. JSTOR2808399.
  27. ^Hull, David L. (December 1967). 'The Metaphysics of Evolution'. The British Journal for the History of Science. 3 (4): 309–337. doi:10.1017/S0007087400002892. JSTOR4024958.
  28. ^Mason 1962, pp. 43–44
  29. ^Mayr 1982, pp. 256–257
  30. ^Waggoner, Ben (July 7, 2000). 'Carl Linnaeus (1707-1778)'. Evolution (Online exhibit). Berkeley, California: University of California Museum of Paleontology. Archived from the original on 2011-04-30. Retrieved 2012-02-11.
  31. ^Bowler 2003, pp. 73–75
  32. ^'Erasmus Darwin (1731-1802)'. Evolution (Online exhibit). Berkeley, California: University of California Museum of Paleontology. October 4, 1995. Archived from the original on 2012-01-19. Retrieved 2012-02-11.
  33. ^Lamarck 1809
  34. ^ abNardon & Grenier 1991, p. 162
  35. ^ abcGould 2002[page needed]
  36. ^Ghiselin, Michael T. (September–October 1994). 'The Imaginary Lamarck: A Look at Bogus 'History' in Schoolbooks'. The Textbook Letter. OCLC23228649. Archived from the original on 2008-02-12. Retrieved 2008-01-23.
  37. ^Magner 2002[page needed]
  38. ^Jablonka, Eva; Lamb, Marion J. (August 2007). 'Précis of Evolution in Four Dimensions'. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 30 (4): 353–365. doi:10.1017/S0140525X07002221. ISSN0140-525X. PMID18081952.
  39. ^Burkhardt & Smith 1991
    • 'Darwin, C. R. to Lubbock, John'. Darwin Correspondence Project. Cambridge, UK: University of Cambridge. Archived from the original on 2014-12-15. Retrieved 2014-12-01. Letter 2532, November 22, 1859.
  40. ^Sulloway, Frank J. (June 2009). 'Why Darwin rejected intelligent design'. Journal of Biosciences. 34 (2): 173–183. doi:10.1007/s12038-009-0020-8. ISSN0250-5991. PMID19550032.
  41. ^Dawkins 1990[page needed]
  42. ^[ http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/search-results?pagesize=50&sort=date-ascending&pageno=0&freetext=descent+with+modification&allfields=&searchid=&name=Darwin+Charles+Robert&dateafter=1859&datebefore=1859&searchtitle=origin&description=&place=&publisher=&periodical= Darwin-Online]
  43. ^Sober, Elliott (June 16, 2009). 'Did Darwin write the Origin backwards?'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106 (Suppl. 1): 10048–10055. Bibcode:2009PNAS..10610048S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0901109106. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2702806. PMID19528655.
  44. ^Mayr 2002, p. 165
  45. ^Bowler 2003, pp. 145–146
  46. ^Sokal, Robert R.; Crovello, Theodore J. (March–April 1970). 'The Biological Species Concept: A Critical Evaluation'. The American Naturalist. 104 (936): 127–153. doi:10.1086/282646. ISSN0003-0147. JSTOR2459191.
  47. ^Darwin, Charles; Wallace, Alfred (August 20, 1858). 'On the Tendency of Species to form Varieties; and on the Perpetuation of Varieties and Species by Natural Means of Selection'. Journal of the Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London. Zoology. 3 (9): 45–62. doi:10.1111/j.1096-3642.1858.tb02500.x. ISSN1096-3642. Archived from the original on 2007-07-14. Retrieved 2007-05-13.
  48. ^Desmond, Adrian J. (July 17, 2014). 'Thomas Henry Huxley'. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Chicago, Illinois: Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc.Archived from the original on January 19, 2015. Retrieved 2014-12-02.
  49. ^Liu, Y. S.; Zhou, X. M.; Zhi, M. X.; Li, X. J.; Wang, Q. L. (September 2009). 'Darwin's contributions to genetics'. Journal of Applied Genetics. 50 (3): 177–184. doi:10.1007/BF03195671. ISSN1234-1983. PMID19638672.
  50. ^Weiling, Franz (July 1991). 'Historical study: Johann Gregor Mendel 1822–1884'. American Journal of Medical Genetics. 40 (1): 1–25, discussion 26. doi:10.1002/ajmg.1320400103. PMID1887835.
  51. ^Wright 1984, p. 480
  52. ^Provine 1971
  53. ^Stamhuis, Ida H.; Meijer, Onno G.; Zevenhuizen, Erik J. A. (June 1999). 'Hugo de Vries on Heredity, 1889-1903: Statistics, Mendelian Laws, Pangenes, Mutations'. Isis. 90 (2): 238–267. doi:10.1086/384323. JSTOR237050. PMID10439561.
  54. ^Quammen 2006[page needed]
  55. ^Bowler 1989[page needed]
  56. ^Watson, J. D.; Crick, F. H. C. (April 25, 1953). 'Molecular Structure of Nucleic Acids: A Structure for Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid'(PDF). Nature. 171 (4356): 737–738. Bibcode:1953Natur.171..737W. doi:10.1038/171737a0. ISSN0028-0836. PMID13054692. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-04. It has not escaped our notice that the specific pairing we have postulated immediately suggests a possible copying mechanism for the genetic material.
  57. ^Hennig 1999, p. 280
  58. ^Wiley & Lieberman 2011[page needed]
  59. ^Dobzhansky, Theodosius (March 1973). 'Nothing in Biology Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution'(PDF). The American Biology Teacher. 35 (3): 125–129. CiteSeerX10.1.1.324.2891. doi:10.2307/4444260. JSTOR4444260. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2015-10-23.
  60. ^ abcKutschera, Ulrich; Niklas, Karl J. (June 2004). 'The modern theory of biological evolution: an expanded synthesis'. Naturwissenschaften. 91 (6): 255–276. Bibcode:2004NW.....91..255K. doi:10.1007/s00114-004-0515-y. ISSN1432-1904. PMID15241603.
  61. ^Cracraft & Bybee 2005[page needed]
  62. ^Avise, John C.; Ayala, Francisco J. (May 11, 2010). 'In the light of evolution IV: The human condition'(PDF). Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107 (Suppl. 2): 8897–8901. doi:10.1073/pnas.1003214107. ISSN0027-8424. PMC3024015. PMID20460311. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-29.
  63. ^Danchin, Étienne; Charmantier, Anne; Champagne, Frances A.; Mesoudi, Alex; Pujol, Benoit; Blanchet, Simon (June 2011). 'Beyond DNA: integrating inclusive inheritance into an extended theory of evolution'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 12 (7): 475–486. doi:10.1038/nrg3028. ISSN1471-0056. PMID21681209.
  64. ^Pigliucci & Müller 2010
  65. ^Sturm, Richard A.; Frudakis, Tony N. (August 2004). 'Eye colour: portals into pigmentation genes and ancestry'. Trends in Genetics. 20 (8): 327–332. doi:10.1016/j.tig.2004.06.010. ISSN0168-9525. PMID15262401.
  66. ^ abPearson, Helen (May 25, 2006). 'Genetics: What is a gene?'. Nature. 441 (7092): 398–401. Bibcode:2006Natur.441..398P. doi:10.1038/441398a. ISSN0028-0836. PMID16724031.
  67. ^Visscher, Peter M.; Hill, William G.; Wray, Naomi R. (April 2008). 'Heritability in the genomics era — concepts and misconceptions'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 9 (4): 255–266. doi:10.1038/nrg2322. ISSN1471-0056. PMID18319743.
  68. ^Oetting, William S.; Brilliant, Murray H.; King, Richard A. (August 1996). 'The clinical spectrum of albinism in humans'. Molecular Medicine Today. 2 (8): 330–335. doi:10.1016/1357-4310(96)81798-9. ISSN1357-4310. PMID8796918.
  69. ^ abFutuyma 2005[page needed]
  70. ^Phillips, Patrick C. (November 2008). 'Epistasis—the essential role of gene interactions in the structure and evolution of genetic systems'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 9 (11): 855–867. doi:10.1038/nrg2452. ISSN1471-0056. PMC2689140. PMID18852697.
  71. ^ abRongling Wu; Min Lin (March 2006). 'Functional mapping — how to map and study the genetic architecture of dynamic complex traits'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 7 (3): 229–237. doi:10.1038/nrg1804. ISSN1471-0056. PMID16485021.
  72. ^Jablonka, Eva; Raz, Gal (June 2009). 'Transgenerational Epigenetic Inheritance: Prevalence, Mechanisms, and Implications for the Study of Heredity and Evolution'(PDF). The Quarterly Review of Biology. 84 (2): 131–176. CiteSeerX10.1.1.617.6333. doi:10.1086/598822. ISSN0033-5770. PMID19606595.
  73. ^Bossdorf, Oliver; Arcuri, Davide; Richards, Christina L.; Pigliucci, Massimo (May 2010). 'Experimental alteration of DNA methylation affects the phenotypic plasticity of ecologically relevant traits in Arabidopsis thaliana'(PDF). Evolutionary Ecology (Submitted manuscript). 24 (3): 541–553. doi:10.1007/s10682-010-9372-7. ISSN0269-7653.
  74. ^Jablonka & Lamb 2005[page needed]
  75. ^Jablonka, Eva; Lamb, Marion J. (December 2002). 'The Changing Concept of Epigenetics'. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 981 (1): 82–96. Bibcode:2002NYASA.981...82J. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.2002.tb04913.x. ISSN0077-8923. PMID12547675.
  76. ^Laland, Kevin N.; Sterelny, Kim (September 2006). 'Perspective: Seven Reasons (Not) to Neglect Niche Construction'. Evolution. 60 (9): 1751–1762. doi:10.1111/j.0014-3820.2006.tb00520.x. ISSN0014-3820.
  77. ^Chapman, Michael J.; Margulis, Lynn (December 1998). 'Morphogenesis by symbiogenesis'(PDF). International Microbiology. 1 (4): 319–326. ISSN1139-6709. PMID10943381. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-09.
  78. ^Wilson, David Sloan; Wilson, Edward O. (December 2007). 'Rethinking the Theoretical Foundation of Sociobiology'(PDF). The Quarterly Review of Biology. 82 (4): 327–348. doi:10.1086/522809. ISSN0033-5770. PMID18217526. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2011-05-11.
  79. ^Amos, William; Harwood, John (February 28, 1998). 'Factors affecting levels of genetic diversity in natural populations'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 353 (1366): 177–186. doi:10.1098/rstb.1998.0200. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1692205. PMID9533122.
  80. ^ abEwens 2004[page needed]
  81. ^Butlin, Roger K.; Tregenza, Tom (February 28, 1998). 'Levels of genetic polymorphism: marker loci versus quantitative traits'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 353 (1366): 187–198. doi:10.1098/rstb.1998.0201. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1692210. PMID9533123.
    • Butlin, Roger K.; Tregenza, Tom (December 29, 2000). 'Correction for Butlin and Tregenza, Levels of genetic polymorphism: marker loci versus quantitative traits'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 355 (1404): 1865. doi:10.1098/rstb.2000.2000. ISSN0962-8436. Some of the values in table 1 on p. 193 were given incorrectly. The errors do not affect the conclusions drawn in the paper. The corrected table is reproduced below.
  82. ^Wetterbom, Anna; Sevov, Marie; Cavelier, Lucia; Bergström, Tomas F. (November 2006). 'Comparative Genomic Analysis of Human and Chimpanzee Indicates a Key Role for Indels in Primate Evolution'. Journal of Molecular Evolution. 63 (5): 682–690. Bibcode:2006JMolE..63..682W. doi:10.1007/s00239-006-0045-7. ISSN0022-2844. PMID17075697.
  83. ^Sawyer, Stanley A.; Parsch, John; Zhang Zhi; Hartl, Daniel L. (April 17, 2007). 'Prevalence of positive selection among nearly neutral amino acid replacements in Drosophila'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (16): 6504–6510. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.6504S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0701572104. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1871816. PMID17409186.
  84. ^Hastings, P. J.; Lupski, James R.; Rosenberg, Susan M.; Ira, Grzegorz (August 2009). 'Mechanisms of change in gene copy number'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 10 (8): 551–564. doi:10.1038/nrg2593. ISSN1471-0056. PMC2864001. PMID19597530.
  85. ^Carroll, Grenier & Weatherbee 2005[page needed]
  86. ^Harrison, Paul M.; Gerstein, Mark (May 17, 2002). 'Studying Genomes Through the Aeons: Protein Families, Pseudogenes and Proteome Evolution'. Journal of Molecular Biology. 318 (5): 1155–1174. doi:10.1016/S0022-2836(02)00109-2. ISSN0022-2836. PMID12083509.
  87. ^Bowmaker, James K. (May 1998). 'Evolution of colour vision in vertebrates'. Eye. 12 (3b): 541–547. doi:10.1038/eye.1998.143. ISSN0950-222X. PMID9775215.
  88. ^Gregory, T. Ryan; Hebert, Paul D. N. (April 1999). 'The Modulation of DNA Content: Proximate Causes and Ultimate Consequences'. Genome Research. 9 (4): 317–324. doi:10.1101/gr.9.4.317 (inactive 2019-06-07). ISSN1088-9051. PMID10207154. Archived from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-11.
  89. ^Hurles, Matthew (July 13, 2004). 'Gene Duplication: The Genomic Trade in Spare Parts'. PLOS Biology. 2 (7): e206. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0020206. ISSN1545-7885. PMC449868. PMID15252449.
  90. ^Liu, Na; Okamura, Katsutomo; Tyler, David M.; et al. (October 2008). 'The evolution and functional diversification of animal microRNA genes'. Cell Research. 18 (10): 985–996. doi:10.1038/cr.2008.278. ISSN1001-0602. PMC2712117. PMID18711447.
  91. ^Siepel, Adam (October 2009). 'Darwinian alchemy: Human genes from noncoding DNA'. Genome Research. 19 (10): 1693–1695. doi:10.1101/gr.098376.109. ISSN1088-9051. PMC2765273. PMID19797681.
  92. ^Orengo, Christine A.; Thornton, Janet M. (July 2005). 'Protein families and their evolution—a structural perspective'. Annual Review of Biochemistry. 74: 867–900. doi:10.1146/annurev.biochem.74.082803.133029. ISSN0066-4154. PMID15954844.
  93. ^Long, Manyuan; Betrán, Esther; Thornton, Kevin; Wang, Wen (November 2003). 'The origin of new genes: glimpses from the young and old'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 4 (11): 865–875. doi:10.1038/nrg1204. ISSN1471-0056. PMID14634634.
  94. ^Wang, Minglei; Caetano-Anollés, Gustavo (January 14, 2009). 'The Evolutionary Mechanics of Domain Organization in Proteomes and the Rise of Modularity in the Protein World'. Structure. 17 (1): 66–78. doi:10.1016/j.str.2008.11.008. ISSN1357-4310. PMID19141283.
  95. ^Weissman, Kira J.; Müller, Rolf (April 14, 2008). 'Protein–Protein Interactions in Multienzyme Megasynthetases'. ChemBioChem. 9 (6): 826–848. doi:10.1002/cbic.200700751. ISSN1439-4227. PMID18357594.
  96. ^Radding, Charles M. (December 1982). 'Homologous Pairing and Strand Exchange in Genetic Recombination'. Annual Review of Genetics. 16: 405–437. doi:10.1146/annurev.ge.16.120182.002201. ISSN0066-4197. PMID6297377.
  97. ^Agrawal, Aneil F. (September 5, 2006). 'Evolution of Sex: Why Do Organisms Shuffle Their Genotypes?'. Current Biology. 16 (17): R696–R704. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2006.07.063. ISSN0960-9822. PMID16950096.
  98. ^Peters, Andrew D.; Otto, Sarah P. (June 2003). 'Liberating genetic variance through sex'. BioEssays. 25 (6): 533–537. doi:10.1002/bies.10291. ISSN0265-9247. PMID12766942.
  99. ^Goddard, Matthew R.; Godfray, H. Charles J.; Burt, Austin (March 31, 2005). 'Sex increases the efficacy of natural selection in experimental yeast populations'. Nature. 434 (7033): 636–640. Bibcode:2005Natur.434..636G. doi:10.1038/nature03405. ISSN0028-0836. PMID15800622.
  100. ^Maynard Smith 1978[page needed]
  101. ^ abRidley 1993[page needed]
  102. ^Van Valen, Leigh (1973). 'A New Evolutionary Law'(PDF). Evolutionary Theory. 1: 1–30. ISSN0093-4755. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2014-12-22. Retrieved 2014-12-24.
  103. ^Hamilton, W. D.; Axelrod, Robert; Tanese, Reiko (May 1, 1990). 'Sexual reproduction as an adaptation to resist parasites (a review)'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 87 (9): 3566–3573. Bibcode:1990PNAS...87.3566H. doi:10.1073/pnas.87.9.3566. ISSN0027-8424. PMC53943. PMID2185476.
  104. ^Birdsell & Wills 2003, pp. 113–117
  105. ^ abMorjan, Carrie L.; Rieseberg, Loren H. (June 2004). 'How species evolve collectively: implications of gene flow and selection for the spread of advantageous alleles'. Molecular Ecology. 13 (6): 1341–1356. doi:10.1111/j.1365-294X.2004.02164.x. ISSN0962-1083. PMC2600545. PMID15140081.
  106. ^Boucher, Yan; Douady, Christophe J.; Papke, R. Thane; et al. (December 2003). 'Lateral gene transfer and the origins of prokaryotic groups'. Annual Review of Genetics. 37: 283–328. doi:10.1146/annurev.genet.37.050503.084247. ISSN0066-4197. PMID14616063.
  107. ^Walsh, Timothy R. (October 2006). 'Combinatorial genetic evolution of multiresistance'. Current Opinion in Microbiology. 9 (5): 476–482. doi:10.1016/j.mib.2006.08.009. ISSN1369-5274. PMID16942901.
  108. ^Kondo, Natsuko; Nikoh, Naruo; Ijichi, Nobuyuki; et al. (October 29, 2002). 'Genome fragment of Wolbachia endosymbiont transferred to X chromosome of host insect'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 99 (22): 14280–14285. Bibcode:2002PNAS...9914280K. doi:10.1073/pnas.222228199. ISSN0027-8424. PMC137875. PMID12386340.
  109. ^Sprague, George F., Jr. (December 1991). 'Genetic exchange between kingdoms'. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development. 1 (4): 530–533. doi:10.1016/S0959-437X(05)80203-5. ISSN0959-437X. PMID1822285.
  110. ^Gladyshev, Eugene A.; Meselson, Matthew; Arkhipova, Irina R. (May 30, 2008). 'Massive Horizontal Gene Transfer in Bdelloid Rotifers'. Science (Submitted manuscript). 320 (5880): 1210–1213. Bibcode:2008Sci...320.1210G. doi:10.1126/science.1156407. ISSN0036-8075. PMID18511688.
  111. ^Baldo, Angela M.; McClure, Marcella A. (September 1999). 'Evolution and Horizontal Transfer of dUTPase-Encoding Genes in Viruses and Their Hosts'. Journal of Virology. 73 (9): 7710–7721. ISSN0022-538X. PMC104298. PMID10438861.
  112. ^Rivera, Maria C.; Lake, James A. (September 9, 2004). 'The ring of life provides evidence for a genome fusion origin of eukaryotes'. Nature. 431 (7005): 152–155. Bibcode:2004Natur.431..152R. doi:10.1038/nature02848. ISSN0028-0836. PMID15356622.
  113. ^ abcHurst, Laurence D. (February 2009). 'Fundamental concepts in genetics: genetics and the understanding of selection'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 10 (2): 83–93. doi:10.1038/nrg2506. ISSN1471-0056. PMID19119264.
  114. ^Darwin 1859, Chapter XIV
  115. ^Otto, Sarah P.; Servedio, Maria R.; Nuismer, Scott L. (August 2008). 'Frequency-Dependent Selection and the Evolution of Assortative Mating'. Genetics. 179 (4): 2091–2112. doi:10.1534/genetics.107.084418. ISSN0016-6731. PMC2516082. PMID18660541.
  116. ^ abcOrr, H. Allen (August 2009). 'Fitness and its role in evolutionary genetics'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 10 (8): 531–539. doi:10.1038/nrg2603. ISSN1471-0056. PMC2753274. PMID19546856.
  117. ^Haldane, J.B.S. (March 14, 1959). 'The Theory of Natural Selection To-Day'. Nature. 183 (4663): 710–713. Bibcode:1959Natur.183..710H. doi:10.1038/183710a0. ISSN0028-0836. PMID13644170.
  118. ^Lande, Russell; Arnold, Stevan J. (November 1983). 'The Measurement of Selection on Correlated Characters'. Evolution. 37 (6): 1210–1226. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.1983.tb00236.x. ISSN0014-3820. JSTOR2408842. PMID28556011.
  119. ^Goldberg, Emma E.; Igić, Boris (November 2008). 'On phylogenetic tests of irreversible evolution'. Evolution. 62 (11): 2727–2741. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2008.00505.x. ISSN0014-3820. PMID18764918.
  120. ^Collin, Rachel; Miglietta, Maria Pia (November 2008). 'Reversing opinions on Dollo's Law'. Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 23 (11): 602–609. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2008.06.013. ISSN0169-5347. PMID18814933.
  121. ^Tomić, Nenad; Meyer-Rochow, Victor Benno (2011). 'Atavisms: Medical, Genetic, and Evolutionary Implications'. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine. 54 (3): 332–353. doi:10.1353/pbm.2011.0034. ISSN0031-5982. PMID21857125.
  122. ^Hoekstra, Hopi E.; Hoekstra, Jonathan M.; Berrigan, David; et al. (July 31, 2001). 'Strength and tempo of directional selection in the wild'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 98 (16): 9157–9160. Bibcode:2001PNAS...98.9157H. doi:10.1073/pnas.161281098. ISSN0027-8424. PMC55389. PMID11470913.
  123. ^Felsenstein, Joseph (November 1979). 'Excursions along the Interface between Disruptive and Stabilizing Selection'. Genetics. 93 (3): 773–795. ISSN0016-6731. PMC1214112. PMID17248980.
  124. ^Andersson, Malte; Simmons, Leigh W. (June 2006). 'Sexual selection and mate choice'(PDF). Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 21 (6): 296–302. CiteSeerX10.1.1.595.4050. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2006.03.015. ISSN0169-5347. PMID16769428. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2013-03-09.
  125. ^Kokko, Hanna; Brooks, Robert; McNamara, John M.; Houston, Alasdair I. (July 7, 2002). 'The sexual selection continuum'. Proceedings of the Royal Society B. 269 (1498): 1331–1340. doi:10.1098/rspb.2002.2020. ISSN0962-8452. PMC1691039. PMID12079655.
  126. ^Quinn, Thomas P.; Hendry, Andrew P.; Buck, Gregory B. (2001). 'Balancing natural and sexual selection in sockeye salmon: interactions between body size, reproductive opportunity and vulnerability to predation by bears'(PDF). Evolutionary Ecology Research. 3: 917–937. ISSN1522-0613. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2016-03-05. Retrieved 2014-12-15.
  127. ^Hunt, John; Brooks, Robert; Jennions, Michael D.; et al. (December 23, 2004). 'High-quality male field crickets invest heavily in sexual display but die young'. Nature. 432 (7020): 1024–1027. Bibcode:2004Natur.432.1024H. doi:10.1038/nature03084. ISSN0028-0836. PMID15616562.
  128. ^Odum 1971, p. 8
  129. ^Okasha 2006
  130. ^ abGould, Stephen Jay (February 28, 1998). 'Gulliver's further travels: the necessity and difficulty of a hierarchical theory of selection'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 353 (1366): 307–314. doi:10.1098/rstb.1998.0211. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1692213. PMID9533127.
  131. ^Mayr, Ernst (March 18, 1997). 'The objects of selection'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 94 (6): 2091–2094. Bibcode:1997PNAS...94.2091M. doi:10.1073/pnas.94.6.2091. ISSN0027-8424. PMC33654. PMID9122151.
  132. ^Maynard Smith 1998, pp. 203–211; discussion 211–217
  133. ^Hickey, Donal A. (1992). 'Evolutionary dynamics of transposable elements in prokaryotes and eukaryotes'. Genetica. 86 (1–3): 269–274. doi:10.1007/BF00133725. ISSN0016-6707. PMID1334911.
  134. ^Gould, Stephen Jay; Lloyd, Elisabeth A. (October 12, 1999). 'Individuality and adaptation across levels of selection: how shall we name and generalise the unit of Darwinism?'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 96 (21): 11904–11909. Bibcode:1999PNAS...9611904G. doi:10.1073/pnas.96.21.11904. ISSN0027-8424. PMC18385. PMID10518549.
  135. ^Lynch, Michael (May 15, 2007). 'The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (Suppl. 1): 8597–8604. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.8597L. doi:10.1073/pnas.0702207104. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1876435. PMID17494740.
  136. ^Smith, Nick G.C.; Webster, Matthew T.; Ellegren, Hans (September 2002). 'Deterministic Mutation Rate Variation in the Human Genome'. Genome Research. 12 (9): 1350–1356. doi:10.1101/gr.220502. ISSN1088-9051. PMC186654. PMID12213772.
  137. ^Petrov, Dmitri A.; Sangster, Todd A.; Johnston, J. Spencer; et al. (February 11, 2000). 'Evidence for DNA Loss as a Determinant of Genome Size'. Science. 287 (5455): 1060–1062. Bibcode:2000Sci...287.1060P. doi:10.1126/science.287.5455.1060. ISSN0036-8075. PMID10669421.
  138. ^Petrov, Dmitri A. (May 2002). 'DNA loss and evolution of genome size in Drosophila'. Genetica. 115 (1): 81–91. doi:10.1023/A:1016076215168. ISSN0016-6707. PMID12188050.
  139. ^Kiontke, Karin; Barrière, Antoine; Kolotuev, Irina; et al. (November 2007). 'Trends, Stasis, and Drift in the Evolution of Nematode Vulva Development'. Current Biology. 17 (22): 1925–1937. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.10.061. ISSN0960-9822. PMID18024125.
  140. ^Braendle, Christian; Baer, Charles F.; Félix, Marie-Anne (March 12, 2010). Barsh, Gregory S. (ed.). 'Bias and Evolution of the Mutationally Accessible Phenotypic Space in a Developmental System'. PLOS Genetics. 6 (3): e1000877. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1000877. ISSN1553-7390. PMC2837400. PMID20300655.
  141. ^Palmer, A. Richard (October 29, 2004). 'Symmetry breaking and the evolution of development'(PDF). Science. 306 (5697): 828–833. Bibcode:2004Sci...306..828P. CiteSeerX10.1.1.631.4256. doi:10.1126/science.1103707. ISSN0036-8075. PMID15514148. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2007-06-12.
  142. ^West-Eberhard 2003, pp. 140
  143. ^Pocheville & Danchin 2017
  144. ^Stoltzfus, Arlin; Yampolsky, Lev Y. (September–October 2009). 'Climbing Mount Probable: Mutation as a Cause of Nonrandomness in Evolution'. Journal of Heredity. 100 (5): 637–647. doi:10.1093/jhered/esp048. ISSN0022-1503. PMID19625453.
  145. ^Yampolsky, Lev Y.; Stoltzfus, Arlin (March 2001). 'Bias in the introduction of variation as an orienting factor in evolution'. Evolution & Development. 3 (2): 73–83. doi:10.1046/j.1525-142x.2001.003002073.x. ISSN1520-541X. PMID11341676.
  146. ^Haldane, J.B.S. (January–February 1933). 'The Part Played by Recurrent Mutation in Evolution'. The American Naturalist. 67 (708): 5–19. doi:10.1086/280465. ISSN0003-0147. JSTOR2457127.
  147. ^Protas, Meredith; Conrad, Melissa; Gross, Joshua B.; et al. (March 6, 2007). 'Regressive Evolution in the Mexican Cave Tetra, Astyanax mexicanus'. Current Biology. 17 (5): 452–454. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.01.051. ISSN0960-9822. PMC2570642. PMID17306543.
  148. ^Maughan, Heather; Masel, Joanna; Birky, C. William, Jr.; Nicholson, Wayne L. (October 2007). 'The Roles of Mutation Accumulation and Selection in Loss of Sporulation in Experimental Populations of Bacillus subtilis'. Genetics. 177 (2): 937–948. doi:10.1534/genetics.107.075663. ISSN0016-6731. PMC2034656. PMID17720926.
  149. ^Masel, Joanna; King, Oliver D.; Maughan, Heather (January 2007). 'The Loss of Adaptive Plasticity during Long Periods of Environmental Stasis'. The American Naturalist. 169 (1): 38–46. doi:10.1086/510212. ISSN0003-0147. PMC1766558. PMID17206583.
  150. ^Futuyma, Douglas J.; Kirkpatrick, Mark (2017). 'Natural selection and adaptation'. Evolution (Fourth ed.). Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates, Inc. pp. 55–66. ISBN978-1-60535-605-1.
  151. ^ abMasel, Joanna (October 25, 2011). 'Genetic drift'. Current Biology. 21 (20): R837–R838. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2011.08.007. ISSN0960-9822. PMID22032182.
  152. ^Lande, Russell (1989). 'Fisherian and Wrightian theories of speciation'. Genome. 31 (1): 221–227. doi:10.1139/g89-037. ISSN0831-2796. PMID2687093.
  153. ^Kimura, Motoo (1991). 'The neutral theory of molecular evolution: a review of recent evidence'. The Japanese Journal of Human Genetics. 66 (4): 367–386. doi:10.1266/jjg.66.367. ISSN0021-504X. PMID1954033.
  154. ^Kimura, Motoo (1989). 'The neutral theory of molecular evolution and the world view of the neutralists'. Genome. 31 (1): 24–31. doi:10.1139/g89-009. ISSN0831-2796. PMID2687096.
  155. ^Kreitman, Martin (August 1996). 'The neutral theory is dead. Long live the neutral theory'. BioEssays. 18 (8): 678–683, discussion 683. doi:10.1002/bies.950180812. ISSN0265-9247. PMID8760341.
  156. ^Leigh, E.G., Jr. (November 2007). 'Neutral theory: a historical perspective'. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 20 (6): 2075–2091. doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01410.x. ISSN1010-061X. PMID17956380.
  157. ^ abGillespie, John H. (November 2001). 'Is the population size of a species relevant to its evolution?'. Evolution. 55 (11): 2161–2169. doi:10.1111/j.0014-3820.2001.tb00732.x. ISSN0014-3820. PMID11794777.
  158. ^Neher, Richard A.; Shraiman, Boris I. (August 2011). 'Genetic Draft and Quasi-Neutrality in Large Facultatively Sexual Populations'. Genetics. 188 (4): 975–996. arXiv:1108.1635. doi:10.1534/genetics.111.128876. ISSN0016-6731. PMC3176096. PMID21625002.
  159. ^Otto, Sarah P.; Whitlock, Michael C. (June 1997). 'The Probability of Fixation in Populations of Changing Size'(PDF). Genetics. 146 (2): 723–733. ISSN0016-6731. PMC1208011. PMID9178020. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2015-03-19. Retrieved 2014-12-18.
  160. ^ abCharlesworth, Brian (March 2009). 'Fundamental concepts in genetics: effective population size and patterns of molecular evolution and variation'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 10 (3): 195–205. doi:10.1038/nrg2526. ISSN1471-0056. PMID19204717.
  161. ^Cutter, Asher D.; Choi, Jae Young (August 2010). 'Natural selection shapes nucleotide polymorphism across the genome of the nematode Caenorhabditis briggsae'. Genome Research. 20 (8): 1103–1111. doi:10.1101/gr.104331.109. ISSN1088-9051. PMC2909573. PMID20508143.
  162. ^Mitchell-Olds, Thomas; Willis, John H.; Goldstein, David B. (November 2007). 'Which evolutionary processes influence natural genetic variation for phenotypic traits?'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 8 (11): 845–856. doi:10.1038/nrg2207. ISSN1471-0056. PMID17943192.
  163. ^Nei, Masatoshi (December 2005). 'Selectionism and Neutralism in Molecular Evolution'. Molecular Biology and Evolution. 22 (12): 2318–2342. doi:10.1093/molbev/msi242. ISSN0737-4038. PMC1513187. PMID16120807.
    • Nei, Masatoshi (May 2006). 'Selectionism and Neutralism in Molecular Evolution'. Molecular Biology and Evolution (Erratum). 23 (5): 1095. doi:10.1093/molbev/msk009. ISSN0737-4038.
  164. ^Lien, Sigbjørn; Szyda, Joanna; Schechinger, Birgit; et al. (February 2000). 'Evidence for Heterogeneity in Recombination in the Human Pseudoautosomal Region: High Resolution Analysis by Sperm Typing and Radiation-Hybrid Mapping'. American Journal of Human Genetics. 66 (2): 557–566. doi:10.1086/302754. ISSN0002-9297. PMC1288109. PMID10677316.
  165. ^Barton, Nicholas H. (November 29, 2000). 'Genetic hitchhiking'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 355 (1403): 1553–1562. doi:10.1098/rstb.2000.0716. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1692896. PMID11127900.
  166. ^Wright, Sewall (1932). 'The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding and selection in evolution'. Proceedings of the VI International Congress of Genetrics. 1: 356–366. Archived from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-18.
  167. ^Coyne, Jerry A.; Barton, Nicholas H.; Turelli, Michael (June 1997). 'Perspective: A Critique of Sewall Wright's Shifting Balance Theory of Evolution'. Evolution. 51 (3): 643–671. doi:10.2307/2411143. ISSN0014-3820. JSTOR2411143. PMID28568586.
  168. ^Baym, Michael; Lieberman, Tami D.; Kelsic, Eric D.; Chait, Remy; Gross, Rotem; Yelin, Idan; Kishony, Roy (2016-09-09). 'Spatiotemporal microbial evolution on antibiotic landscapes'. Science. 353 (6304): 1147–1151. Bibcode:2016Sci...353.1147B. doi:10.1126/science.aag0822. ISSN0036-8075. PMC5534434. PMID27609891.
  169. ^ abcScott, Eugenie C.; Matzke, Nicholas J. (May 15, 2007). 'Biological design in science classrooms'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (Suppl. 1): 8669–8676. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.8669S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0701505104. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1876445. PMID17494747.
  170. ^Hendry, Andrew Paul; Kinnison, Michael T. (November 2001). 'An introduction to microevolution: rate, pattern, process'. Genetica. 112–113 (1): 1–8. doi:10.1023/A:1013368628607. ISSN0016-6707. PMID11838760.
  171. ^Leroi, Armand M. (March–April 2000). 'The scale independence of evolution'. Evolution & Development. 2 (2): 67–77. CiteSeerX10.1.1.120.1020. doi:10.1046/j.1525-142x.2000.00044.x. ISSN1520-541X. PMID11258392.
  172. ^Gould 2002, pp. 657–658.
  173. ^ abGould, Stephen Jay (July 19, 1994). 'Tempo and mode in the macroevolutionary reconstruction of Darwinism'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 91 (15): 6764–6771. Bibcode:1994PNAS...91.6764G. doi:10.1073/pnas.91.15.6764. ISSN0027-8424. PMC44281. PMID8041695.
  174. ^Jablonski, David (2000). 'Micro- and macroevolution: scale and hierarchy in evolutionary biology and paleobiology'. Paleobiology. 26 (sp4): 15–52. doi:10.1666/0094-8373(2000)26[15:MAMSAH]2.0.CO;2. ISSN0094-8373.
  175. ^Dougherty, Michael J. (July 20, 1998). 'Is the human race evolving or devolving?'. Scientific American. ISSN0036-8733. Archived from the original on 2014-05-06. Retrieved 2015-09-11.
  176. ^Isaak, Mark, ed. (July 22, 2003). 'Claim CB932: Evolution of degenerate forms'. TalkOrigins Archive. Houston, Texas: The TalkOrigins Foundation, Inc. Archived from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-19.
  177. ^Lane 1996, p. 61
  178. ^Carroll, Sean B. (February 22, 2001). 'Chance and necessity: the evolution of morphological complexity and diversity'. Nature. 409 (6823): 1102–1109. Bibcode:2001Natur.409.1102C. doi:10.1038/35059227. ISSN0028-0836. PMID11234024.
  179. ^Whitman, William B.; Coleman, David C.; Wiebe, William J. (June 9, 1998). 'Prokaryotes: The unseen majority'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 95 (12): 6578–6583. Bibcode:1998PNAS...95.6578W. doi:10.1073/pnas.95.12.6578. ISSN0027-8424. PMC33863. PMID9618454.
  180. ^ abSchloss, Patrick D.; Handelsman, Jo (December 2004). 'Status of the Microbial Census'. Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews. 68 (4): 686–691. doi:10.1128/MMBR.68.4.686-691.2004. ISSN1092-2172. PMC539005. PMID15590780.
  181. ^Nealson, Kenneth H. (January 1999). 'Post-Viking microbiology: new approaches, new data, new insights'. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres. 29 (1): 73–93. doi:10.1023/A:1006515817767. ISSN0169-6149. PMID11536899.
  182. ^Buckling, Angus; MacLean, R. Craig; Brockhurst, Michael A.; Colegrave, Nick (February 12, 2009). 'The Beagle in a bottle'. Nature. 457 (7231): 824–829. Bibcode:2009Natur.457..824B. doi:10.1038/nature07892. ISSN0028-0836. PMID19212400.
  183. ^Elena, Santiago F.; Lenski, Richard E. (June 2003). 'Evolution experiments with microorganisms: the dynamics and genetic bases of adaptation'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 4 (6): 457–469. doi:10.1038/nrg1088. ISSN1471-0056. PMID12776215.
  184. ^Mayr 1982, p. 483: 'Adaptation... could no longer be considered a static condition, a product of a creative past and became instead a continuing dynamic process.'
  185. ^The sixth edition of the Oxford Dictionary of Science (2010) defines adaptation as 'Any change in the structure or functioning of successive generations of a population that makes it better suited to its environment.'
  186. ^Orr, H. Allen (February 2005). 'The genetic theory of adaptation: a brief history'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 6 (2): 119–127. doi:10.1038/nrg1523. ISSN1471-0056. PMID15716908.
  187. ^Dobzhansky 1968, pp. 1–34
  188. ^Dobzhansky 1970, pp. 4–6, 79–82, 84–87
  189. ^Dobzhansky, Theodosius (March 1956). 'Genetics of Natural Populations. XXV. Genetic Changes in Populations of Drosophila pseudoobscura and Drosophila persimilis in Some Localities in California'. Evolution. 10 (1): 82–92. doi:10.2307/2406099. ISSN0014-3820. JSTOR2406099.
  190. ^Nakajima, Akira; Sugimoto, Yohko; Yoneyama, Hiroshi; Nakae, Taiji (June 2002). 'High-Level Fluoroquinolone Resistance in Pseudomonas aeruginosa Due to Interplay of the MexAB-OprM Efflux Pump and the DNA Gyrase Mutation'. Microbiology and Immunology. 46 (6): 391–395. doi:10.1111/j.1348-0421.2002.tb02711.x. ISSN1348-0421. PMID12153116.
  191. ^Blount, Zachary D.; Borland, Christina Z.; Lenski, Richard E. (June 10, 2008). 'Inaugural Article: Historical contingency and the evolution of a key innovation in an experimental population of Escherichia coli'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105 (23): 7899–7906. Bibcode:2008PNAS..105.7899B. doi:10.1073/pnas.0803151105. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2430337. PMID18524956.
  192. ^Okada, Hirosuke; Negoro, Seiji; Kimura, Hiroyuki; Nakamura, Shunichi (November 10, 1983). 'Evolutionary adaptation of plasmid-encoded enzymes for degrading nylon oligomers'. Nature. 306 (5939): 203–206. Bibcode:1983Natur.306..203O. doi:10.1038/306203a0. ISSN0028-0836. PMID6646204.
  193. ^Ohno, Susumu (April 1984). 'Birth of a unique enzyme from an alternative reading frame of the preexisted, internally repetitious coding sequence'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 81 (8): 2421–2425. Bibcode:1984PNAS...81.2421O. doi:10.1073/pnas.81.8.2421. ISSN0027-8424. PMC345072. PMID6585807.
  194. ^Copley, Shelley D. (June 2000). 'Evolution of a metabolic pathway for degradation of a toxic xenobiotic: the patchwork approach'. Trends in Biochemical Sciences. 25 (6): 261–265. doi:10.1016/S0968-0004(00)01562-0. ISSN0968-0004. PMID10838562.
  195. ^Crawford, Ronald L.; Jung, Carina M.; Strap, Janice L. (October 2007). 'The recent evolution of pentachlorophenol (PCP)-4-monooxygenase (PcpB) and associated pathways for bacterial degradation of PCP'. Biodegradation. 18 (5): 525–539. doi:10.1007/s10532-006-9090-6. ISSN0923-9820. PMID17123025.
  196. ^Eshel, Ilan (December 1973). 'Clone-Selection and Optimal Rates of Mutation'. Journal of Applied Probability. 10 (4): 728–738. doi:10.2307/3212376. ISSN1475-6072. JSTOR3212376.
  197. ^Altenberg 1995, pp. 205–259
  198. ^Masel, Joanna; Bergman, Aviv (July 2003). 'The evolution of the evolvability properties of the yeast prion [PSI+]'. Evolution. 57 (7): 1498–1512. doi:10.1111/j.0014-3820.2003.tb00358.x. ISSN0014-3820. PMID12940355.
  199. ^Lancaster, Alex K.; Bardill, J. Patrick; True, Heather L.; Masel, Joanna (February 2010). 'The Spontaneous Appearance Rate of the Yeast Prion [PSI+] and Its Implications for the Evolution of the Evolvability Properties of the [PSI+] System'. Genetics. 184 (2): 393–400. doi:10.1534/genetics.109.110213. ISSN0016-6731. PMC2828720. PMID19917766.
  200. ^Draghi, Jeremy; Wagner, Günter P. (February 2008). 'Evolution of evolvability in a developmental model'. Evolution. 62 (2): 301–315. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2007.00303.x. ISSN0014-3820. PMID18031304.
  201. ^ abBejder, Lars; Hall, Brian K. (November 2002). 'Limbs in whales and limblessness in other vertebrates: mechanisms of evolutionary and developmental transformation and loss'. Evolution & Development. 4 (6): 445–458. doi:10.1046/j.1525-142X.2002.02033.x. ISSN1520-541X. PMID12492145.
  202. ^Young, Nathan M.; HallgrÍmsson, Benedikt (December 2005). 'Serial homology and the evolution of mammalian limb covariation structure'. Evolution. 59 (12): 2691–2704. doi:10.1554/05-233.1. ISSN0014-3820. PMID16526515.
  203. ^ abPenny, David; Poole, Anthony (December 1999). 'The nature of the last universal common ancestor'. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development. 9 (6): 672–677. doi:10.1016/S0959-437X(99)00020-9. ISSN0959-437X. PMID10607605.
  204. ^Hall, Brian K. (August 2003). 'Descent with modification: the unity underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through an analysis of development and evolution'. Biological Reviews. 78 (3): 409–433. doi:10.1017/S1464793102006097. ISSN1464-7931. PMID14558591.
  205. ^Shubin, Neil; Tabin, Clifford J.; Carroll, Sean B. (February 12, 2009). 'Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty'. Nature. 457 (7231): 818–823. Bibcode:2009Natur.457..818S. doi:10.1038/nature07891. ISSN0028-0836. PMID19212399.
  206. ^ abcFong, Daniel F.; Kane, Thomas C.; Culver, David C. (November 1995). 'Vestigialization and Loss of Nonfunctional Characters'. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics. 26: 249–268. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.26.110195.001341. ISSN1545-2069.
  207. ^ZhaoLei Zhang; Gerstein, Mark (August 2004). 'Large-scale analysis of pseudogenes in the human genome'. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development. 14 (4): 328–335. doi:10.1016/j.gde.2004.06.003. ISSN0959-437X. PMID15261647.
  208. ^Jeffery, William R. (May–June 2005). 'Adaptive Evolution of Eye Degeneration in the Mexican Blind Cavefish'. Journal of Heredity. 96 (3): 185–196. doi:10.1093/jhered/esi028. ISSN0022-1503. PMID15653557.
  209. ^Maxwell, Erin E.; Larsson, Hans C.E. (May 2007). 'Osteology and myology of the wing of the Emu (Dromaius novaehollandiae) and its bearing on the evolution of vestigial structures'. Journal of Morphology. 268 (5): 423–441. doi:10.1002/jmor.10527. ISSN0362-2525. PMID17390336.
  210. ^van der Kooi, Casper J.; Schwander, Tanja (November 2014). 'On the fate of sexual traits under asexuality'(PDF). Biological Reviews. 89 (4): 805–819. doi:10.1111/brv.12078. ISSN1464-7931. PMID24443922. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2015-07-23. Retrieved 2015-08-05.
  211. ^Silvestri, Anthony R., Jr.; Singh, Iqbal (April 2003). 'The unresolved problem of the third molar: Would people be better off without it?'. Journal of the American Dental Association. 134 (4): 450–455. doi:10.14219/jada.archive.2003.0194. ISSN0002-8177. PMID12733778. Archived from the original on 2014-08-23.
  212. ^Coyne 2009, p. 62
  213. ^Darwin 1872, pp. 101, 103
  214. ^Gray 2007, p. 66
  215. ^Coyne 2009, pp. 85–86
  216. ^Stevens 1982, p. 87
  217. ^ abGould 2002, pp. 1235–1236.
  218. ^Pallen, Mark J.; Matzke, Nicholas J. (October 2006). 'From The Origin of Species to the origin of bacterial flagella'(PDF). Nature Reviews Microbiology (PDF). 4 (10): 784–790. doi:10.1038/nrmicro1493. ISSN1740-1526. PMID16953248. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2014-12-26. Retrieved 2014-12-25.
  219. ^Clements, Abigail; Bursac, Dejan; Gatsos, Xenia; et al. (September 15, 2009). 'The reducible complexity of a mitochondrial molecular machine'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106 (37): 15791–15795. Bibcode:2009PNAS..10615791C. doi:10.1073/pnas.0908264106. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2747197. PMID19717453.
  220. ^Piatigorsky et al. 1994, pp. 241–250
  221. ^Wistow, Graeme (August 1993). 'Lens crystallins: gene recruitment and evolutionary dynamism'. Trends in Biochemical Sciences. 18 (8): 301–306. doi:10.1016/0968-0004(93)90041-K. ISSN0968-0004. PMID8236445.
  222. ^Johnson, Norman A.; Porter, Adam H. (November 2001). 'Toward a new synthesis: population genetics and evolutionary developmental biology'. Genetica. 112–113 (1): 45–58. doi:10.1023/A:1013371201773. ISSN0016-6707. PMID11838782.
  223. ^Baguñà, Jaume; Garcia-Fernàndez, Jordi (2003). 'Evo-Devo: the long and winding road'. The International Journal of Developmental Biology. 47 (7–8): 705–713. ISSN0214-6282. PMID14756346. Archived from the original on 2014-11-28.
    • Love, Alan C. (March 2003). 'Evolutionary Morphology, Innovation and the Synthesis of Evolutionary and Developmental Biology'. Biology and Philosophy. 18 (2): 309–345. doi:10.1023/A:1023940220348. ISSN0169-3867.
  224. ^Allin, Edgar F. (December 1975). 'Evolution of the mammalian middle ear'. Journal of Morphology. 147 (4): 403–437. doi:10.1002/jmor.1051470404. ISSN0362-2525. PMID1202224.
  225. ^Harris, Matthew P.; Hasso, Sean M.; Ferguson, Mark W.J.; Fallon, John F. (February 21, 2006). 'The Development of Archosaurian First-Generation Teeth in a Chicken Mutant'. Current Biology. 16 (4): 371–377. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2005.12.047. ISSN0960-9822. PMID16488870.
  226. ^Carroll, Sean B. (July 11, 2008). 'Evo-Devo and an Expanding Evolutionary Synthesis: A Genetic Theory of Morphological Evolution'. Cell. 134 (1): 25–36. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2008.06.030. ISSN0092-8674. PMID18614008.
  227. ^Wade, Michael J. (March 2007). 'The co-evolutionary genetics of ecological communities'. Nature Reviews Genetics. 8 (3): 185–195. doi:10.1038/nrg2031. ISSN1471-0056. PMID17279094.
  228. ^Geffeney, Shana; Brodie, Edmund D., Jr.; Ruben, Peter C.; Brodie, Edmund D., III (August 23, 2002). 'Mechanisms of Adaptation in a Predator-Prey Arms Race: TTX-Resistant Sodium Channels'. Science. 297 (5585): 1336–1339. Bibcode:2002Sci...297.1336G. doi:10.1126/science.1074310. ISSN0036-8075. PMID12193784.
    • Brodie, Edmund D., Jr.; Ridenhour, Benjamin J.; Brodie, Edmund D., III (October 2002). 'The evolutionary response of predators to dangerous prey: hotspots and coldspots in the geographic mosaic of coevolution between garter snakes and newts'. Evolution. 56 (10): 2067–2082. doi:10.1554/0014-3820(2002)056[2067:teropt]2.0.co;2. ISSN0014-3820. PMID12449493.
    • Carroll, Sean B. (December 21, 2009). 'Whatever Doesn't Kill Some Animals Can Make Them Deadly'. The New York Times. New York: The New York Times Company. ISSN0362-4331. Archived from the original on 2015-04-23. Retrieved 2014-12-26.
  229. ^Sachs, Joel L. (September 2006). 'Cooperation within and among species'. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 19 (5): 1415–1418, discussion 1426–1436. doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2006.01152.x. ISSN1010-061X. PMID16910971.
    • Nowak, Martin A. (December 8, 2006). 'Five Rules for the Evolution of Cooperation'. Science. 314 (5805): 1560–1563. Bibcode:2006Sci...314.1560N. doi:10.1126/science.1133755. ISSN0036-8075. PMC3279745. PMID17158317.
  230. ^Paszkowski, Uta (August 2006). 'Mutualism and parasitism: the yin and yang of plant symbioses'. Current Opinion in Plant Biology. 9 (4): 364–370. doi:10.1016/j.pbi.2006.05.008. ISSN1369-5266. PMID16713732.
  231. ^Hause, Bettina; Fester, Thomas (May 2005). 'Molecular and cell biology of arbuscular mycorrhizal symbiosis'. Planta. 221 (2): 184–196. doi:10.1007/s00425-004-1436-x. ISSN0032-0935. PMID15871030.
  232. ^Bertram, John S. (December 2000). 'The molecular biology of cancer'. Molecular Aspects of Medicine. 21 (6): 167–223. doi:10.1016/S0098-2997(00)00007-8. ISSN0098-2997. PMID11173079.
  233. ^Reeve, H. Kern; Hölldobler, Bert (June 5, 2007). 'The emergence of a superorganism through intergroup competition'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (23): 9736–9740. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.9736R. doi:10.1073/pnas.0703466104. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1887545. PMID17517608.
  234. ^Axelrod, Robert; Hamilton, W. D. (March 27, 1981). 'The evolution of cooperation'. Science. 211 (4489): 1390–1396. Bibcode:1981Sci...211.1390A. doi:10.1126/science.7466396. ISSN0036-8075. PMID7466396.
  235. ^Wilson, Edward O.; Hölldobler, Bert (September 20, 2005). 'Eusociality: Origin and consequences'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102 (38): 13367–1371. Bibcode:2005PNAS..10213367W. doi:10.1073/pnas.0505858102. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1224642. PMID16157878.
  236. ^ abGavrilets, Sergey (October 2003). 'Perspective: models of speciation: what have we learned in 40 years?'. Evolution. 57 (10): 2197–2215. doi:10.1554/02-727. ISSN0014-3820. PMID14628909.
  237. ^ abcde Queiroz, Kevin (May 3, 2005). 'Ernst Mayr and the modern concept of species'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102 (Suppl. 1): 6600–6607. Bibcode:2005PNAS..102.6600D. doi:10.1073/pnas.0502030102. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1131873. PMID15851674.
  238. ^ abEreshefsky, Marc (December 1992). 'Eliminative pluralism'. Philosophy of Science. 59 (4): 671–690. doi:10.1086/289701. ISSN0031-8248. JSTOR188136.
  239. ^Mayr 1942, p. 120
  240. ^Fraser, Christophe; Alm, Eric J.; Polz, Martin F.; et al. (February 6, 2009). 'The Bacterial Species Challenge: Making Sense of Genetic and Ecological Diversity'. Science. 323 (5915): 741–746. Bibcode:2009Sci...323..741F. doi:10.1126/science.1159388. ISSN0036-8075. PMID19197054.
  241. ^Short, Roger Valentine (October 1975). 'The contribution of the mule to scientific thought'. Journal of Reproduction and Fertility. Supplement (23): 359–364. ISSN0449-3087. OCLC1639439. PMID1107543.
  242. ^Gross, Briana L.; Rieseberg, Loren H. (May–June 2005). 'The Ecological Genetics of Homoploid Hybrid Speciation'. Journal of Heredity. 96 (3): 241–252. doi:10.1093/jhered/esi026. ISSN0022-1503. PMC2517139. PMID15618301.
  243. ^Burke, John M.; Arnold, Michael L. (December 2001). 'Genetics and the fitness of hybrids'. Annual Review of Genetics. 35: 31–52. doi:10.1146/annurev.genet.35.102401.085719. ISSN0066-4197. PMID11700276.
  244. ^Vrijenhoek, Robert C. (April 4, 2006). 'Polyploid Hybrids: Multiple Origins of a Treefrog Species'. Current Biology. 16 (7): R245–R247. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2006.03.005. ISSN0960-9822. PMID16581499.
  245. ^Rice, William R.; Hostert, Ellen E. (December 1993). 'Laboratory Experiments on Speciation: What Have We Learned in 40 Years?'. Evolution. 47 (6): 1637–1653. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.1993.tb01257.x. ISSN0014-3820. JSTOR2410209. PMID28568007.
    • Jiggins, Chris D.; Bridle, Jon R. (March 2004). 'Speciation in the apple maggot fly: a blend of vintages?'. Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 19 (3): 111–114. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2003.12.008. ISSN0169-5347. PMID16701238.
    • Boxhorn, Joseph (September 1, 1995). 'Observed Instances of Speciation'. TalkOrigins Archive. Houston, Texas: The TalkOrigins Foundation, Inc. Archived from the original on 2009-01-22. Retrieved 2008-12-26.
    • Weinberg, James R.; Starczak, Victoria R.; Jörg, Daniele (August 1992). 'Evidence for Rapid Speciation Following a Founder Event in the Laboratory'. Evolution. 46 (4): 1214–1220. doi:10.2307/2409766. ISSN0014-3820. JSTOR2409766. PMID28564398.
  246. ^Herrel, Anthony; Huyghe, Katleen; Vanhooydonck, Bieke; et al. (March 25, 2008). 'Rapid large-scale evolutionary divergence in morphology and performance associated with exploitation of a different dietary resource'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105 (12): 4792–4795. Bibcode:2008PNAS..105.4792H. doi:10.1073/pnas.0711998105. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2290806. PMID18344323.
  247. ^Losos, Jonathan B.; Warhelt, Kenneth I.; Schoener, Thomas W. (May 1, 1997). 'Adaptive differentiation following experimental island colonization in Anolis lizards'. Nature. 387 (6628): 70–73. Bibcode:1997Natur.387...70L. doi:10.1038/387070a0. ISSN0028-0836.
  248. ^Hoskin, Conrad J.; Higgle, Megan; McDonald, Keith R.; Moritz, Craig (October 27, 2005). 'Reinforcement drives rapid allopatric speciation'. Nature. 437 (7063): 1353–1356. Bibcode:2005Natur.437.1353H. doi:10.1038/nature04004. ISSN0028-0836. PMID16251964.
  249. ^Templeton, Alan R. (April 1980). 'The Theory of Speciation VIA the Founder Principle'. Genetics. 94 (4): 1011–1038. ISSN0016-6731. PMC1214177. PMID6777243. Archived from the original on 2014-08-23. Retrieved 2014-12-29.
  250. ^Antonovics, Janis (July 2006). 'Evolution in closely adjacent plant populations X: long-term persistence of prereproductive isolation at a mine boundary'. Heredity. 97 (1): 33–37. doi:10.1038/sj.hdy.6800835. ISSN0018-067X. PMID16639420.
  251. ^Nosil, Patrik; Crespi, Bernard J.; Gries, Regine; Gries, Gerhard (March 2007). 'Natural selection and divergence in mate preference during speciation'. Genetica. 129 (3): 309–327. doi:10.1007/s10709-006-0013-6. ISSN0016-6707. PMID16900317.
  252. ^Savolainen, Vincent; Anstett, Marie-Charlotte; Lexer, Christian; et al. (May 11, 2006). 'Sympatric speciation in palms on an oceanic island'. Nature. 441 (7090): 210–213. Bibcode:2006Natur.441..210S. doi:10.1038/nature04566. ISSN0028-0836. PMID16467788.
    • Barluenga, Marta; Stölting, Kai N.; Salzburger, Walter; et al. (February 9, 2006). 'Sympatric speciation in Nicaraguan crater lake cichlid fish'. Nature. 439 (7077): 719–23. Bibcode:2006Natur.439..719B. doi:10.1038/nature04325. ISSN0028-0836. PMID16467837.
  253. ^Gavrilets, Sergey (March 21, 2006). 'The Maynard Smith model of sympatric speciation'. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 239 (2): 172–182. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2005.08.041. ISSN0022-5193. PMID16242727.
  254. ^Wood, Troy E.; Takebayashi, Naoki; Barker, Michael S.; et al. (August 18, 2009). 'The frequency of polyploid speciation in vascular plants'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106 (33): 13875–13879. Bibcode:2009PNAS..10613875W. doi:10.1073/pnas.0811575106. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2728988. PMID19667210.
  255. ^Hegarty, Matthew J.; Hiscock, Simon J. (May 20, 2008). 'Genomic Clues to the Evolutionary Success of Polyploid Plants'. Current Biology. 18 (10): R435–R444. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2008.03.043. ISSN0960-9822. PMID18492478.
  256. ^Jakobsson, Mattias; Hagenblad, Jenny; Tavaré, Simon; et al. (June 2006). 'A Unique Recent Origin of the Allotetraploid Species Arabidopsis suecica: Evidence from Nuclear DNA Markers'. Molecular Biology and Evolution. 23 (6): 1217–1231. doi:10.1093/molbev/msk006. ISSN0737-4038. PMID16549398.
  257. ^Säll, Torbjörn; Jakobsson, Mattias; Lind-Halldén, Christina; Halldén, Christer (September 2003). 'Chloroplast DNA indicates a single origin of the allotetraploid Arabidopsis suecica'. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 16 (5): 1019–1029. doi:10.1046/j.1420-9101.2003.00554.x. ISSN1010-061X. PMID14635917.
  258. ^Bomblies, Kirsten; Weigel, Detlef (December 2007). 'Arabidopsis—a model genus for speciation'. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development. 17 (6): 500–504. doi:10.1016/j.gde.2007.09.006. ISSN0959-437X. PMID18006296.
  259. ^Sémon, Marie; Wolfe, Kenneth H. (December 2007). 'Consequences of genome duplication'. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development. 17 (6): 505–512. doi:10.1016/j.gde.2007.09.007. ISSN0959-437X. PMID18006297.
  260. ^Eldredge & Gould 1972, pp. 82–115
  261. ^Benton, Michael J. (April 7, 1995). 'Diversification and extinction in the history of life'. Science. 268 (5207): 52–58. Bibcode:1995Sci...268...52B. doi:10.1126/science.7701342. ISSN0036-8075. PMID7701342.
  262. ^Raup, David M. (March 28, 1986). 'Biological extinction in Earth history'. Science. 231 (4745): 1528–1533. Bibcode:1986Sci...231.1528R. doi:10.1126/science.11542058. ISSN0036-8075. PMID11542058.
  263. ^Avise, John C.; Hubbell, Stephen P.; Ayala, Francisco J. (August 12, 2008). 'In the light of evolution II: Biodiversity and extinction'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105 (Suppl. 1): 11453–11457. Bibcode:2008PNAS..10511453A. doi:10.1073/pnas.0802504105. ISSN0027-8424. PMC2556414. PMID18695213.
  264. ^ abcRaup, David M. (July 19, 1994). 'The role of extinction in evolution'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 91 (15): 6758–6763. Bibcode:1994PNAS...91.6758R. doi:10.1073/pnas.91.15.6758. ISSN0027-8424. PMC44280. PMID8041694.
  265. ^Novacek, Michael J.; Cleland, Elsa E. (May 8, 2001). 'The current biodiversity extinction event: scenarios for mitigation and recovery'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 98 (10): 5466–5470. Bibcode:2001PNAS...98.5466N. doi:10.1073/pnas.091093698. ISSN0027-8424. PMC33235. PMID11344295.
  266. ^Pimm, Stuart; Raven, Peter; Peterson, Alan; et al. (July 18, 2006). 'Human impacts on the rates of recent, present and future bird extinctions'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103 (29): 10941–10946. Bibcode:2006PNAS..10310941P. doi:10.1073/pnas.0604181103. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1544153. PMID16829570.
    • Barnosky, Anthony D.; Koch, Paul L.; Feranec, Robert S.; et al. (October 1, 2004). 'Assessing the Causes of Late Pleistocene Extinctions on the Continents'. Science. 306 (5693): 70–75. Bibcode:2004Sci...306...70B. CiteSeerX10.1.1.574.332. doi:10.1126/science.1101476. ISSN0036-8075. PMID15459379.
  267. ^Lewis, Owen T. (January 29, 2006). 'Climate change, species–area curves and the extinction crisis'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 361 (1465): 163–171. doi:10.1098/rstb.2005.1712. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1831839. PMID16553315.
  268. ^ abStearns & Stearns 1999, p. X
  269. ^ abNovacek, Michael J. (November 8, 2014). 'Prehistory's Brilliant Future'. The New York Times. New York: The New York Times Company. ISSN0362-4331. Archived from the original on 2014-12-29. Retrieved 2014-12-25.
  270. ^'Researchers find that Earth may be home to 1 trillion species'. National Science Foundation. Arlington County, Virginia. May 2, 2016. Archived from the original on 2016-05-04. Retrieved 2016-05-06.
  271. ^Jablonski, David (May 8, 2001). 'Lessons from the past: Evolutionary impacts of mass extinctions'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 98 (10): 5393–5398. Bibcode:2001PNAS...98.5393J. doi:10.1073/pnas.101092598. ISSN0027-8424. PMC33224. PMID11344284.
  272. ^'Age of the Earth'. United States Geological Survey. July 9, 2007. Archived from the original on 2005-12-23. Retrieved 2015-05-31.
  273. ^Dalrymple 2001, pp. 205–221
  274. ^Manhesa, Gérard; Allègre, Claude J.; Dupréa, Bernard; Hamelin, Bruno (May 1980). 'Lead isotope study of basic-ultrabasic layered complexes: Speculations about the age of the earth and primitive mantle characteristics'. Earth and Planetary Science Letters. 47 (3): 370–382. Bibcode:1980E&PSL..47..370M. doi:10.1016/0012-821X(80)90024-2. ISSN0012-821X.
  275. ^Raven & Johnson 2002, p. 68
  276. ^ abBorenstein, Seth (19 October 2015). 'Hints of life on what was thought to be desolate early Earth'. Excite. Yonkers, NY: Mindspark Interactive Network. Associated Press. Archived from the original on 23 October 2015. Retrieved 8 October 2018.
  277. ^Bell, Elizabeth A.; Boehnike, Patrick; Harrison, T. Mark; Mao, Wendy L. (November 24, 2015). 'Potentially biogenic carbon preserved in a 4.1 billion-year-old zircon'(PDF). Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 112 (47): 14518–14521. Bibcode:2015PNAS..11214518B. doi:10.1073/pnas.1517557112. ISSN0027-8424. PMC4664351. PMID26483481. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2015-11-06. Retrieved 2015-12-30.
  278. ^Schouten, Lucy (October 20, 2015). 'When did life first emerge on Earth? Maybe a lot earlier than we thought'. The Christian Science Monitor. Boston, Massachusetts: Christian Science Publishing Society. ISSN0882-7729. Archived from the original on 2016-03-22. Retrieved 2018-07-11.
  279. ^Wade, Nicholas (July 25, 2016). 'Meet Luca, the Ancestor of All Living Things'. The New York Times. New York: The New York Times Company. ISSN0362-4331. Archived from the original on July 28, 2016. Retrieved 2016-07-25.
  280. ^McKinney 1997, p. 110
  281. ^Mora, Camilo; Tittensor, Derek P.; Adl, Sina; et al. (August 23, 2011). 'How Many Species Are There on Earth and in the Ocean?'. PLOS Biology. 9 (8): e1001127. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001127. ISSN1545-7885. PMC3160336. PMID21886479.
  282. ^Miller & Spoolman 2012, p. 62
  283. ^Chapman 2009
  284. ^Roskov, Y.; Abucay, L.; Orrell, T.; Nicolson, D.; et al., eds. (2016). 'Species 2000 & ITIS Catalogue of Life, 2016 Annual Checklist'. Species 2000. Leiden, Netherlands: Naturalis Biodiversity Center. ISSN2405-884X. Archived from the original on 2016-11-12. Retrieved 2016-11-06.
  285. ^Peretó, Juli (March 2005). 'Controversies on the origin of life'(PDF). International Microbiology. 8 (1): 23–31. ISSN1139-6709. PMID15906258. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2015-08-24.
  286. ^Joyce, Gerald F. (July 11, 2002). 'The antiquity of RNA-based evolution'. Nature. 418 (6894): 214–221. Bibcode:2002Natur.418..214J. doi:10.1038/418214a. ISSN0028-0836. PMID12110897.
  287. ^Trevors, Jack T.; Psenner, Roland (December 2001). 'From self-assembly of life to present-day bacteria: a possible role for nanocells'. FEMS Microbiology Reviews. 25 (5): 573–582. doi:10.1111/j.1574-6976.2001.tb00592.x. ISSN1574-6976. PMID11742692.
  288. ^Theobald, Douglas L. (May 13, 2010). 'A formal test of the theory of universal common ancestry'. Nature. 465 (7295): 219–222. Bibcode:2010Natur.465..219T. doi:10.1038/nature09014. ISSN0028-0836. PMID20463738.
  289. ^Bapteste, Eric; Walsh, David A. (June 2005). 'Does the 'Ring of Life' ring true?'. Trends in Microbiology. 13 (6): 256–261. doi:10.1016/j.tim.2005.03.012. ISSN0966-842X. PMID15936656.
  290. ^Darwin 1859, p. 1
  291. ^Doolittle, W. Ford; Bapteste, Eric (February 13, 2007). 'Pattern pluralism and the Tree of Life hypothesis'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (7): 2043–2049. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.2043D. doi:10.1073/pnas.0610699104. ISSN0027-8424. PMC1892968. PMID17261804.
  292. ^Kunin, Victor; Goldovsky, Leon; Darzentas, Nikos; Ouzounis, Christos A. (July 2005). 'The net of life: Reconstructing the microbial phylogenetic network'. Genome Research. 15 (7): 954–959. doi:10.1101/gr.3666505. ISSN1088-9051. PMC1172039. PMID15965028.
  293. ^Darwin, Charles (1837). Notebook B. p. 25.
  294. ^Jablonski, David (June 25, 1999). 'The Future of the Fossil Record'. Science. 284 (5423): 2114–2116. doi:10.1126/science.284.5423.2114. ISSN0036-8075. PMID10381868.
  295. ^Mason, Stephen F. (September 6, 1984). 'Origins of biomolecular handedness'. Nature. 311 (5981): 19–23. Bibcode:1984Natur.311...19M. doi:10.1038/311019a0. ISSN0028-0836. PMID6472461.
  296. ^Wolf, Yuri I.; Rogozin, Igor B.; Grishin, Nick V.; Koonin, Eugene V. (September 1, 2002). 'Genome trees and the tree of life'. Trends in Genetics. 18 (9): 472–479. doi:10.1016/S0168-9525(02)02744-0. ISSN0168-9525. PMID12175808.
  297. ^Varki, Ajit; Altheide, Tasha K. (December 2005). 'Comparing the human and chimpanzee genomes: searching for needles in a haystack'. Genome Research. 15 (12): 1746–1758. doi:10.1101/gr.3737405. ISSN1088-9051. PMID16339373.
  298. ^Ciccarelli, Francesca D.; Doerks, Tobias; von Mering, Christian; et al. (March 3, 2006). 'Toward Automatic Reconstruction of a Highly Resolved Tree of Life'(PDF). Science. 311 (5765): 1283–1287. Bibcode:2006Sci...311.1283C. CiteSeerX10.1.1.381.9514. doi:10.1126/science.1123061. ISSN0036-8075. PMID16513982. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2016-03-04.
  299. ^ abCavalier-Smith, Thomas (June 29, 2006). 'Cell evolution and Earth history: stasis and revolution'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 361 (1470): 969–1006. doi:10.1098/rstb.2006.1842. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1578732. PMID16754610.
  300. ^Schopf, J. William (June 29, 2006). 'Fossil evidence of Archaean life'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 361 (1470): 869–885. doi:10.1098/rstb.2006.1834. ISSN0962-8436. PMC1578735. PMID16754604.
    • Altermann, Wladyslaw; Kazmierczak, Józef (November 2003). 'Archean microfossils: a reappraisal of early life on Earth'. Research in Microbiology. 154 (9): 611–617. doi:10.1016/j.resmic.2003.08.006. ISSN0923-2508. PMID14596897.
  301. ^Schopf, J. William (July 19, 1994). 'Disparate rates, differing fates: tempo and mode of evolution changed from the Precambrian to the Phanerozoic'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 91 (15): 6735–6742. Bibcode:1994PNAS...91.6735S. doi:10.1073/pnas.91.15.6735. ISSN0027-8424. PMC44277. PMID8041691.
  302. ^Poole, Anthony M.; Penny, David (January 2007). 'Evaluating hypotheses for the origin of eukaryotes'. BioEssays. 29 (1): 74–84. doi:10.1002/bies.20516. ISSN0265-9247. PMID17187354.
  303. ^Dyall, Sabrina D.; Brown, Mark T.; Johnson, Patricia J. (April 9, 2004). 'Ancient Invasions: From Endosymbionts to Organelles'. Science. 304 (5668): 253–257. Bibcode:2004Sci...304..253D. doi:10.1126/science.1094884. ISSN0036-8075. PMID15073369.
  304. ^Martin, William (October 2005). 'The missing link between hydrogenosomes and mitochondria'. Trends in Microbiology. 13 (10): 457–459. doi:10.1016/j.tim.2005.08.005. ISSN0966-842X. PMID16109488.
  305. ^Lang, B. Franz; Gray, Michael W.; Burger, Gertraud (December 1999). 'Mitochondrial genome evolution and the origin of eukaryotes'. Annual Review of Genetics. 33: 351–397. doi:10.1146/annurev.genet.33.1.351. ISSN0066-4197. PMID10690412.
    • McFadden, Geoffrey Ian (December 1, 1999). 'Endosymbiosis and evolution of the plant cell'. Current Opinion in Plant Biology. 2 (6): 513–519. doi:10.1016/S1369-5266(99)00025-4. ISSN1369-5266. PMID10607659.
  306. ^DeLong, Edward F.; Pace, Norman R. (August 1, 2001). 'Environmental Diversity of Bacteria and Archaea'(PDF). Systematic Biology. 50 (4): 470–478. CiteSeerX10.1.1.321.8828. doi:10.1080/106351501750435040. ISSN1063-5157. PMID12116647. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2016-02-22.
  307. ^Kaiser, Dale (December 2001). 'Building a multicellular organism'. Annual Review of Genetics. 35: 103–123. doi:10.1146/annurev.genet.35.102401.090145. ISSN0066-4197. PMID11700279.
  308. ^Zimmer, Carl (January 7, 2016). 'Genetic Flip Helped Organisms Go From One Cell to Many'. The New York Times. New York: The New York Times Company. ISSN0362-4331. Archived from the original on 2016-01-07. Retrieved 2016-01-07.
  309. ^Valentine, James W.; Jablonski, David; Erwin, Douglas H. (March 1, 1999). 'Fossils, molecules and embryos: new perspectives on the Cambrian explosion'. Development. 126 (5): 851–859. ISSN0950-1991. PMID9927587. Archived from the original on 2015-03-01. Retrieved 2014-12-30.
  310. ^Ohno, Susumu (January 1997). 'The reason for as well as the consequence of the Cambrian explosion in animal evolution'. Journal of Molecular Evolution. 44 (Suppl. 1): S23–S27. Bibcode:1997JMolE..44S..23O. doi:10.1007/PL00000055. ISSN0022-2844. PMID9071008.
    • Valentine, James W.; Jablonski, David (2003). 'Morphological and developmental macroevolution: a paleontological perspective'. The International Journal of Developmental Biology. 47 (7–8): 517–522. ISSN0214-6282. PMID14756327. Archived from the original on 2014-10-24. Retrieved 2014-12-30.
  311. ^Waters, Elizabeth R. (December 2003). 'Molecular adaptation and the origin of land plants'. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution. 29 (3): 456–463. doi:10.1016/j.ympev.2003.07.018. ISSN1055-7903. PMID14615186.
  312. ^Mayhew, Peter J. (August 2007). 'Why are there so many insect species? Perspectives from fossils and phylogenies'. Biological Reviews. 82 (3): 425–454. doi:10.1111/j.1469-185X.2007.00018.x. ISSN1464-7931. PMID17624962.
  313. ^Carroll, Robert L. (May 2007). 'The Palaeozoic Ancestry of Salamanders, Frogs and Caecilians'. Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society. 150 (Supplement s1): 1–140. doi:10.1111/j.1096-3642.2007.00246.x. ISSN1096-3642.
  314. ^Wible, John R.; Rougier, Guillermo W.; Novacek, Michael J.; Asher, Robert J. (June 21, 2007). 'Cretaceous eutherians and Laurasian origin for placental mammals near the K/T boundary'. Nature. 447 (7147): 1003–1006. Bibcode:2007Natur.447.1003W. doi:10.1038/nature05854. ISSN0028-0836. PMID17581585.
  315. ^Witmer, Lawrence M. (July 28, 2011). 'Palaeontology: An icon knocked from its perch'. Nature. 475 (7357): 458–459. doi:10.1038/475458a. ISSN0028-0836. PMID21796198.
  316. ^Bull, James J.; Wichman, Holly A. (November 2001). 'Applied evolution'. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics. 32: 183–217. doi:10.1146/annurev.ecolsys.32.081501.114020. ISSN1545-2069.
  317. ^Doebley, John F.; Gaut, Brandon S.; Smith, Bruce D. (December 29, 2006). 'The Molecular Genetics of Crop Domestication'. Cell. 127 (7): 1309–1321. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2006.12.006. ISSN0092-8674. PMID17190597.
  318. ^Jäckel, Christian; Kast, Peter; Hilvert, Donald (June 2008). 'Protein Design by Directed Evolution'. Annual Review of Biophysics. 37: 153–173. doi:10.1146/annurev.biophys.37.032807.125832. ISSN1936-122X. PMID18573077.
  319. ^Maher, Brendan (April 8, 2009). 'Evolution: Biology's next top model?'. Nature. 458 (7239): 695–698. doi:10.1038/458695a. ISSN0028-0836. PMID19360058.
  320. ^Borowsky, Richard (January 8, 2008). 'Restoring sight in blind cavefish'. Current Biology. 18 (1): R23–R24. Bibcode:1996CBio....6.1213A. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.11.023. ISSN0960-9822. PMID18177707.
  321. ^Gross, Joshua B.; Borowsky, Richard; Tabin, Clifford J. (January 2, 2009). Barsh, Gregory S. (ed.). 'A novel role for Mc1r in the parallel evolution of depigmentation in independent populations of the cavefish Astyanax mexicanus'. PLOS Genetics. 5 (1): e1000326. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1000326. ISSN1553-7390. PMC2603666. PMID19119422.
  322. ^Merlo, Lauren M.F.; Pepper, John W.; Reid, Brian J.; Maley, Carlo C. (December 2006). 'Cancer as an evolutionary and ecological process'. Nature Reviews Cancer. 6 (12): 924–935. doi:10.1038/nrc2013. ISSN1474-175X. PMID17109012.
  323. ^Pan, Dabo; Weiwei Xue; Wenqi Zhang; et al. (October 2012). 'Understanding the drug resistance mechanism of hepatitis C virus NS3/4A to ITMN-191 due to R155K, A156V, D168A/E mutations: a computational study'. Biochimica et Biophysica Acta (BBA) - General Subjects. 1820 (10): 1526–1534. doi:10.1016/j.bbagen.2012.06.001. ISSN0304-4165. PMID22698669.
  324. ^Woodford, Neil; Ellington, Matthew J. (January 2007). 'The emergence of antibiotic resistance by mutation'. Clinical Microbiology and Infection. 13 (1): 5–18. doi:10.1111/j.1469-0691.2006.01492.x. ISSN1198-743X. PMID17184282.
  325. ^Labbé, Pierrick; Berticat, Claire; Berthomieu, Arnaud; et al. (November 16, 2007). 'Forty Years of Erratic Insecticide Resistance Evolution in the Mosquito Culex pipiens'. PLOS Genetics. 3 (11): e205. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.0030205. ISSN1553-7390. PMC2077897. PMID18020711.
  326. ^Neve, Paul (October 2007). 'Challenges for herbicide resistance evolution and management: 50 years after Harper'. Weed Research. 47 (5): 365–369. doi:10.1111/j.1365-3180.2007.00581.x. ISSN0043-1737.
  327. ^Rodríguez-Rojas, Alexandro; Rodríguez-Beltrán, Jerónimo; Couce, Alejandro; Blázquez, Jesús (August 2013). 'Antibiotics and antibiotic resistance: A bitter fight against evolution'. International Journal of Medical Microbiology. 303 (6–7): 293–297. doi:10.1016/j.ijmm.2013.02.004. ISSN1438-4221. PMID23517688.
  328. ^Schenk, Martijn F.; Szendro, Ivan G.; Krug, Joachim; de Visser, J. Arjan G.M. (June 28, 2012). 'Quantifying the Adaptive Potential of an Antibiotic Resistance Enzyme'. PLOS Genetics. 8 (6): e1002783. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1002783. ISSN1553-7390. PMC3386231. PMID22761587.
  329. ^Read, Andrew F.; Lynch, Penelope A.; Thomas, Matthew B. (April 7, 2009). 'How to Make Evolution-Proof Insecticides for Malaria Control'. PLOS Biology. 7 (4): e1000058. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1000058. ISSN1545-7885. PMC3279047. PMID19355786.
  330. ^Fraser, Alex S. (January 18, 1958). 'Monte Carlo Analyses of Genetic Models'. Nature. 181 (4603): 208–209. Bibcode:1958Natur.181..208F. doi:10.1038/181208a0. ISSN0028-0836. PMID13504138.
  331. ^Rechenberg 1973
  332. ^Holland 1975
  333. ^Koza 1992
  334. ^Jamshidi, Mo (August 15, 2003). 'Tools for intelligent control: fuzzy controllers, neural networks and genetic algorithms'. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A. 361 (1809): 1781–1808. Bibcode:2003RSPTA.361.1781J. doi:10.1098/rsta.2003.1225. ISSN1364-503X. PMID12952685.
  335. ^Browne 2003, pp. 376–379
  336. ^For an overview of the philosophical, religious and cosmological controversies, see:For the scientific and social reception of evolution in the 19th and early 20th centuries, see:
    • Johnston, Ian C. (1999). 'Section Three: The Origins of Evolutionary Theory'. ... And Still We Evolve: A Handbook for the Early History of Modern Science (3rd revised ed.). Nanaimo, BC: Liberal Studies Department, Malaspina University-College. Archived from the original on 2016-04-16. Retrieved 2015-01-01.
    • Zuckerkandl, Emile (December 30, 2006). 'Intelligent design and biological complexity'. Gene. 385: 2–18. doi:10.1016/j.gene.2006.03.025. ISSN0378-1119. PMID17011142.
  337. ^Ross, Marcus R. (May 2005). 'Who Believes What? Clearing up Confusion over Intelligent Design and Young-Earth Creationism'(PDF). Journal of Geoscience Education. 53 (3): 319–323. Bibcode:2005JGeEd..53..319R. CiteSeerX10.1.1.404.1340. doi:10.5408/1089-9995-53.3.319. ISSN1089-9995. Archived(PDF) from the original on 2008-05-11. Retrieved 2008-04-28.
  338. ^Hameed, Salman (December 12, 2008). 'Bracing for Islamic Creationism'(PDF). Science. 322 (5908): 1637–1638. doi:10.1126/science.1163672. ISSN0036-8075. PMID19074331. Archived from the original(PDF) on 2014-11-10.
  339. ^Bowler 2003
  340. ^Miller, Jon D.; Scott, Eugenie C.; Okamoto, Shinji (August 11, 2006). 'Public Acceptance of Evolution'. Science. 313 (5788): 765–766. doi:10.1126/science.1126746. ISSN0036-8075. PMID16902112.
  341. ^Spergel, David Nathaniel; Verde, Licia; Peiris, Hiranya V.; et al. (2003). 'First-Year Wilkinson Microwave Anisotropy Probe (WMAP) Observations: Determination of Cosmological Parameters'. The Astrophysical Journal Supplement Series. 148 (1): 175–194. arXiv:astro-ph/0302209. Bibcode:2003ApJS..148..175S. doi:10.1086/377226.
  342. ^Wilde, Simon A.; Valley, John W.; Peck, William H.; Graham, Colin M. (January 11, 2001). 'Evidence from detrital zircons for the existence of continental crust and oceans on the Earth 4.4 Gyr ago'. Nature. 409 (6817): 175–178. doi:10.1038/35051550. ISSN0028-0836. PMID11196637.
  343. ^Branch, Glenn (March 2007). 'Understanding Creationism after Kitzmiller'. BioScience. 57 (3): 278–284. Bibcode:1985BioSc..35..499W. doi:10.1641/B570313. ISSN0006-3568.
  344. ^https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/british-journal-for-the-history-of-science/article/translation-and-transmutation-the-origin-of-species-in-china/3F5AED9F9D60EF2D7265927BB2B6AB3A

Bibliography

Mader 10th Edition Biology Pdf

  • Altenberg, Lee (1995). 'Genome growth and the evolution of the genotype-phenotype map'. In Banzhaf, Wolfgang; Eeckman, Frank H. (eds.). Evolution and Biocomputation: Computational Models of Evolution. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. 899. Berlin; New York: Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 205–259. CiteSeerX10.1.1.493.6534. doi:10.1007/3-540-59046-3_11. ISBN978-3-540-59046-0. ISSN0302-9743. LCCN95005970. OCLC32049812.
  • Ayala, Francisco J.; Avise, John C., eds. (2014). Essential Readings in Evolutionary Biology. Baltimore, Maryland: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN978-1-4214-1305-1. LCCN2013027718. OCLC854285705.
  • Birdsell, John A.; Wills, Christopher (2003). 'The Evolutionary Origin and Maintenance of Sexual Recombination: A Review of Contemporary Models'. In MacIntyre, Ross J.; Clegg, Michael T. (eds.). Evolutionary Biology. Evolutionary Biology. 33. New York: Springer Science+Business Media. ISBN978-1-4419-3385-0. ISSN0071-3260. OCLC751583918.
  • Bowler, Peter J. (1989). The Mendelian Revolution: The Emergence of Hereditarian Concepts in Modern Science and Society. Baltimore, Maryland: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN978-0-8018-3888-0. LCCN89030914. OCLC19322402.
  • Bowler, Peter J. (2003). Evolution: The History of an Idea (3rd completely rev. and expanded ed.). Berkeley, California: University of California Press. ISBN978-0-520-23693-6. LCCN2002007569. OCLC49824702.
  • Browne, Janet (2003). Charles Darwin: The Power of Place. 2. London: Pimlico. ISBN978-0-7126-6837-8. LCCN94006598. OCLC52327000.
  • Burkhardt, Frederick; Smith, Sydney, eds. (1991). The Correspondence of Charles Darwin. The Correspondence of Charles Darwin. 7: 1858–1859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-38564-0. LCCN84045347. OCLC185662993.
  • Carroll, Sean B.; Grenier, Jennifer K.; Weatherbee, Scott D. (2005). From DNA to Diversity: Molecular Genetics and the Evolution of Animal Design (2nd ed.). Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing. ISBN978-1-4051-1950-4. LCCN2003027991. OCLC53972564.
  • Chapman, Arthur D. (2009). Numbers of Living Species in Australia and the World (2nd ed.). Canberra: Department of the Environment, Water, Heritage and the Arts: Australian Biological Resources Study. ISBN978-0-642-56860-1. OCLC780539206. Archived from the original on 2016-12-25. Retrieved 2016-11-06.
  • Coyne, Jerry A. (2009). Why Evolution is True. New York: Viking. ISBN978-0-670-02053-9. LCCN2008033973. OCLC233549529.
  • Cracraft, Joel; Bybee, Rodger W., eds. (2005). Evolutionary Science and Society: Educating a New Generation(PDF). Colorado Springs, Colorado: Biological Sciences Curriculum Study. ISBN978-1-929614-23-3. OCLC64228003. Retrieved 2014-12-06. 'Revised Proceedings of the BSCS, AIBS Symposium November 2004, Chicago, Illinois'
  • Dalrymple, G. Brent (2001). 'The age of the Earth in the twentieth century: a problem (mostly) solved'. In Lewis, C.L.E.; Knell, S.J. (eds.). The Age of the Earth: from 4004 BC to AD 2002. Geological Society, London, Special Publications. Geological Society Special Publication. 190. pp. 205–221. Bibcode:2001GSLSP.190..205D. doi:10.1144/gsl.sp.2001.190.01.14. ISBN978-1-86239-093-5. LCCN2003464816. OCLC48570033.
  • Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (1st ed.). London: John Murray. LCCN06017473. OCLC741260650. The book is available from The Complete Work of Charles Darwin Online. Retrieved 2014-11-21.
  • Darwin, Charles (1872). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. London: John Murray. LCCN04002793. OCLC1102785.
  • Darwin, Francis, ed. (1909). The foundations of The origin of species, a sketch written in 1842(PDF). Cambridge: Printed at the University Press. LCCN61057537. OCLC1184581. Retrieved 2014-11-27.
  • Dawkins, Richard (1990). The Blind Watchmaker. Penguin Science. London: Penguin Books. ISBN978-0-14-014481-9. OCLC60143870.
  • Dennett, Daniel (1995). Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon & Schuster. ISBN978-0-684-80290-9. LCCN94049158. OCLC31867409.
  • Dobzhansky, Theodosius (1968). 'On Some Fundamental Concepts of Darwinian Biology'. In Dobzhansky, Theodosius; Hecht, Max K.; Steere, William C. (eds.). Evolutionary Biology. Volume 2 (1st ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. pp. 1–34. doi:10.1007/978-1-4684-8094-8_1. ISBN978-1-4684-8096-2. OCLC24875357.
  • Dobzhansky, Theodosius (1970). Genetics of the Evolutionary Process. New York: Columbia University Press. ISBN978-0-231-02837-0. LCCN72127363. OCLC97663.
  • Eldredge, Niles; Gould, Stephen Jay (1972). 'Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism'. In Schopf, Thomas J.M. (ed.). Models in Paleobiology. San Francisco, California: Freeman, Cooper. ISBN978-0-87735-325-6. LCCN72078387. OCLC572084.
    • Eldredge, Niles (1985). Time Frames: The Rethinking of Darwinian Evolution and the Theory of Punctuated Equilibria. New York: Simon & Schuster. ISBN978-0-671-49555-8. LCCN84023632. OCLC11443805.
  • Ewens, Warren J. (2004). Mathematical Population Genetics. Interdisciplinary Applied Mathematics. I. Theoretical Introduction (2nd ed.). New York: Springer-Verlag New York. ISBN978-0-387-20191-7. LCCN2003065728. OCLC53231891.
  • Futuyma, Douglas J. (2004). 'The Fruit of the Tree of Life: Insights into Evolution and Ecology'. In Cracraft, Joel; Donoghue, Michael J. (eds.). Assembling the Tree of Life. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-517234-8. LCCN2003058012. OCLC61342697. 'Proceedings of a symposium held at the American Museum of Natural History in New York, 2002.'
  • Futuyma, Douglas J. (2005). Evolution. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates. ISBN978-0-87893-187-3. LCCN2004029808. OCLC57311264.
  • Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN978-0-674-00613-3. LCCN2001043556. OCLC47869352.
  • Gray, Peter (2007). Psychology (5th ed.). New York: Worth Publishers. ISBN978-0-7167-0617-5. LCCN2006921149. OCLC76872504.
  • Hall, Brian K.; Hallgrímsson, Benedikt (2008). Strickberger's Evolution (4th ed.). Sudbury, Massachusetts: Jones and Bartlett Publishers. ISBN978-0-7637-0066-9. LCCN2007008981. OCLC85814089.
  • Hennig, Willi (1999) [Originally published 1966 (reprinted 1979); translated from the author's unpublished revision of Grundzüge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik, published in 1950]. Phylogenetic Systematics. Translation by D. Dwight Davis and Rainer Zangerl; foreword by Donn E. Rosen, Gareth Nelson, and Colin Patterson (Reissue ed.). Urbana, Illinois: University of Illinois Press. ISBN978-0-252-06814-0. LCCN78031969. OCLC722701473.
  • Holland, John H. (1975). Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems: An Introductory Analysis with Applications to Biology, Control, and Artificial Intelligence. Ann Arbor, Michigan: University of Michigan Press. ISBN978-0-472-08460-9. LCCN74078988. OCLC1531617.
  • Jablonka, Eva; Lamb, Marion J. (2005). Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Illustrations by Anna Zeligowski. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN978-0-262-10107-3. LCCN2004058193. OCLC61896061.
  • Kampourakis, Kostas (2014). Understanding Evolution. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-1-107-03491-4. LCCN2013034917. OCLC855585457.
  • Kirk, Geoffrey; Raven, John; Schofield, Malcolm (1983). The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts (2nd ed.). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-27455-5. LCCN82023505. OCLC9081712.
  • Koza, John R. (1992). Genetic Programming: On the Programming of Computers by Means of Natural Selection. Complex Adaptive Systems. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN978-0-262-11170-6. LCCN92025785. OCLC26263956.
  • Lamarck, Jean-Baptiste (1809). Philosophie Zoologique. Paris: Dentu et L'Auteur. OCLC2210044.Philosophie zoologique (1809) at the Internet Archive. Retrieved 2014-11-29.
  • Lane, David H. (1996). The Phenomenon of Teilhard: Prophet for a New Age (1st ed.). Macon, Georgia: Mercer University Press. ISBN978-0-86554-498-7. LCCN96008777. OCLC34710780.
  • Lucretius. 'Book V, lines 855–877'. De Rerum Natura. Perseus Digital Library. Edited and translated by William Ellery Leonard (1916). Medford/Somerville, Massachusetts: Tufts University. OCLC33233743. Archived from the original on 2014-09-04. Retrieved 2014-11-25.
  • Magner, Lois N. (2002). A History of the Life Sciences (3rd rev. and expanded ed.). New York: Marcel Dekker. ISBN978-0-8247-0824-5. LCCN2002031313. OCLC50410202.
  • Mason, Stephen F. (1962). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. Science Library, CS9 (New rev. ed.). New York: Collier Books. LCCN62003378. OCLC568032626.
  • Maynard Smith, John (1978). The Evolution of Sex. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-29302-0. LCCN77085689. OCLC3413793.
  • Maynard Smith, John (1998). 'The Units of Selection'. In Bock, Gregory R.; Goode, Jamie A. (eds.). The Limits of Reductionism in Biology. Novartis Foundation Symposium. Novartis Foundation Symposia. 213. Chichester, England: John Wiley & Sons. pp. 203–221. doi:10.1002/9780470515488.ch15. ISBN978-0-471-97770-4. LCCN98002779. OCLC38311600. PMID9653725. 'Papers from the Symposium on the Limits of Reductionism in Biology, held at the Novartis Foundation, London, May 13–15, 1997.'
  • Mayr, Ernst (1942). Systematics and the Origin of Species from the Viewpoint of a Zoologist. Columbia Biological Series. 13. New York: Columbia University Press. LCCN43001098. OCLC766053.
  • Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Translation of John Ray by E. Silk. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press. ISBN978-0-674-36445-5. LCCN81013204. OCLC7875904.
  • Mayr, Ernst (2002) [Originally published 2001; New York: Basic Books]. What Evolution Is. Science Masters. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. ISBN978-0-297-60741-0. LCCN2001036562. OCLC248107061.
  • McKinney, Michael L. (1997). 'How do rare species avoid extinction? A paleontological view'. In Kunin, William E.; Gaston, Kevin J. (eds.). The Biology of Rarity: Causes and consequences of rare—common differences (1st ed.). London; New York: Chapman & Hall. ISBN978-0-412-63380-5. LCCN96071014. OCLC36442106.
  • Miller, G. Tyler; Spoolman, Scott E. (2012). Environmental Science (14th ed.). Belmont, California: Brooks/Cole. ISBN978-1-111-98893-7. LCCN2011934330. OCLC741539226. Retrieved 2014-12-27.
  • Moore, Randy; Decker, Mark; Cotner, Sehoya (2010). Chronology of the Evolution-Creationism Controversy. Santa Barbara, California: Greenwood Press/ABC-CLIO. ISBN978-0-313-36287-3. LCCN2009039784. OCLC422757410.
  • Nardon, Paul; Grenier, Anne-Marie (1991). 'Serial Endosymbiosis Theory and Weevil Evolution: The Role of Symbiosis'. In Margulis, Lynn; Fester, René (eds.). Symbiosis as a Source of Evolutionary Innovation: Speciation and Morphogenesis. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN978-0-262-13269-5. LCCN90020439. OCLC22597587. 'Based on a conference held in Bellagio, Italy, June 25–30, 1989'
  • National Academy of Sciences; Institute of Medicine (2008). Science, Evolution, and Creationism. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. ISBN978-0-309-10586-6. LCCN2007015904. OCLC123539346. Retrieved 2014-11-22.
  • Odum, Eugene P. (1971). Fundamentals of Ecology (3rd ed.). Philadelphia, Pennsylvania: Saunders. ISBN978-0-7216-6941-0. LCCN76081826. OCLC154846.
  • Okasha, Samir (2006). Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-926797-2. LCCN2006039679. OCLC70985413.
  • Panno, Joseph (2005). The Cell: Evolution of the First Organism. Facts on File science library. New York: Facts on File. ISBN978-0-8160-4946-2. LCCN2003025841. OCLC53901436.
  • Piatigorsky, Joram; Kantorow, Marc; Gopal-Srivastava, Rashmi; Tomarev, Stanislav I. (1994). 'Recruitment of enzymes and stress proteins as lens crystallins'. In Jansson, Bengt; Jörnvall, Hans; Rydberg, Ulf; et al. (eds.). Toward a Molecular Basis of Alcohol Use and Abuse. Exs. Experientia. 71. Basel; Boston: Birkhäuser Verlag. pp. 241–50. doi:10.1007/978-3-0348-7330-7_24. ISBN978-3-7643-2940-2. LCCN94010167. OCLC30030941. PMID8032155.
  • Pigliucci, Massimo; Müller, Gerd B., eds. (2010). Evolution, the Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN978-0-262-51367-8. LCCN2009024587. OCLC804875316. Archived from the original on 2015-09-18.
  • Pocheville, Arnaud; Danchin, Étienne (2017). 'Chapter 3: Genetic assimilation and the paradox of blind variation'. In Huneman, Philippe; Walsh, Denis M. (eds.). Challenging the Modern Synthesis. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-937717-6. LCCN2017448929. OCLC1001337947.
  • Provine, William B. (1971). The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago History of Science and Medicine (2nd ed.). Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. ISBN978-0-226-68464-2. LCCN2001027561. OCLC46660910.
  • Provine, William B. (1988). 'Progress in Evolution and Meaning in Life'. In Nitecki, Matthew H. (ed.). Evolutionary Progress. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. ISBN978-0-226-58693-9. LCCN88020835. OCLC18380658. 'This book is the result of the Spring Systematics Symposium held in May, 1987, at the Field Museum in Chicago'
  • Quammen, David (2006). The Reluctant Mr. Darwin: An Intimate Portrait of Charles Darwin and the Making of His Theory of Evolution. Great Discoveries (1st ed.). New York: Atlas Books/W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN978-0-393-05981-6. LCCN2006009864. OCLC65400177.
  • Raven, Peter H.; Johnson, George B. (2002). Biology (6th ed.). Boston, Massachusetts: McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-112261-0. LCCN2001030052. OCLC45806501.
  • Ray, John (1686). Historia Plantarum [History of Plants]. I. Londini: Typis Mariæ Clark. LCCNagr11000774. OCLC2126030.
  • Rechenberg, Ingo (1973). Evolutionsstrategie; Optimierung technischer Systeme nach Prinzipien der biologischen Evolution (PhD thesis). Problemata (in German). 15. Afterword by Manfred Eigen. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog. ISBN978-3-7728-0373-4. LCCN74320689. OCLC9020616.
  • Ridley, Matt (1993). The Red Queen: Sex and the Evolution of Human Nature. New York: Viking. ISBN978-0-670-84357-2. OCLC636657988.
  • Stearns, Beverly Peterson; Stearns, Stephen C. (1999). Watching, from the Edge of Extinction. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press. ISBN978-0-300-08469-6. LCCN98034087. OCLC803522914.
  • Stevens, Anthony (1982). Archetype: A Natural History of the Self. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. ISBN978-0-7100-0980-7. LCCN84672250. OCLC10458367.
  • West-Eberhard, Mary Jane (2003). Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-512235-0. LCCN2001055164. OCLC48398911.
  • Wiley, E. O.; Lieberman, Bruce S. (2011). Phylogenetics: Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics (2nd ed.). Hoboken, New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9781118017883. ISBN978-0-470-90596-8. LCCN2010044283. OCLC741259265.
  • Wright, Sewall (1984). Genetic and Biometric Foundations. Evolution and the Genetics of Populations. 1. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. ISBN978-0-226-91038-3. LCCN67025533. OCLC246124737.

Further reading

Library resources about
Evolution

Introductory reading

  • Barrett, Paul H.; Weinshank, Donald J.; Gottleber, Timothy T., eds. (1981). A Concordance to Darwin's Origin of Species, First Edition. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press. ISBN978-0-8014-1319-3. LCCN80066893. OCLC610057960.
  • Carroll, Sean B. (2005). Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo Devo and the Making of the Animal Kingdom. illustrations by Jamie W. Carroll, Josh P. Klaiss, Leanne M. Olds (1st ed.). New York: W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN978-0-393-06016-4. LCCN2004029388. OCLC57316841.
  • Charlesworth, Brian; Charlesworth, Deborah (2003). Evolution: A Very Short Introduction. Very Short Introductions. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-280251-4. LCCN2003272247. OCLC51668497.
  • Gould, Stephen Jay (1989). Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History (1st ed.). New York: W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN978-0-393-02705-1. LCCN88037469. OCLC18983518.
  • Jones, Steve (1999). Almost Like a Whale: The Origin of Species Updated. London; New York: Doubleday. ISBN978-0-385-40985-8. LCCN2002391059. OCLC41420544.
    • —— (2000). Darwin's Ghost: The Origin of Species Updated (1st ed.). New York: Random House. ISBN978-0-375-50103-6. LCCN99053246. OCLC42690131. American version.
  • Mader, Sylvia S. (2007). Biology. Significant contributions by Murray P. Pendarvis (9th ed.). Boston, Massachusetts: McGraw-Hill Higher Education. ISBN978-0-07-246463-4. LCCN2005027781. OCLC61748307.
  • Maynard Smith, John (1993). The Theory of Evolution (Canto ed.). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-45128-4. LCCN93020358. OCLC27676642.
  • Pallen, Mark J. (2009). The Rough Guide to Evolution. Rough Guides Reference Guides. London; New York: Rough Guides. ISBN978-1-85828-946-5. LCCN2009288090. OCLC233547316.

Advanced reading

  • Barton, Nicholas H.; Briggs, Derek E.G.; Eisen, Jonathan A.; et al. (2007). Evolution. Cold Spring Harbor, New York: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press. ISBN978-0-87969-684-9. LCCN2007010767. OCLC86090399.
  • Coyne, Jerry A.; Orr, H. Allen (2004). Speciation. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates. ISBN978-0-87893-089-0. LCCN2004009505. OCLC55078441.
  • Bergstrom, Carl T.; Dugatkin, Lee Alan (2012). Evolution (1st ed.). New York: W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN978-0-393-91341-5. LCCN2011036572. OCLC729341924.
  • Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN978-0-674-00613-3. LCCN2001043556. OCLC47869352.
  • Hall, Brian K.; Olson, Wendy, eds. (2003). Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN978-0-674-00904-2. LCCN2002192201. OCLC50761342.
  • Kauffman, Stuart A. (1993). The Origins of Order: Self-organization and Selection in Evolution. New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-19-507951-7. LCCN91011148. OCLC895048122.
  • Maynard Smith, John; Szathmáry, Eörs (1995). The Major Transitions in Evolution. Oxford; New York: W.H. Freeman Spektrum. ISBN978-0-7167-4525-9. LCCN94026965. OCLC30894392.
  • Mayr, Ernst (2001). What Evolution Is. New York: Basic Books. ISBN978-0-465-04426-9. LCCN2001036562. OCLC47443814.
  • Minelli, Alessandro (2009). Forms of Becoming: The Evolutionary Biology of Development. Translation by Mark Epstein. Princeton, New Jersey; Oxford: Princeton University Press. ISBN978-0-691-13568-7. LCCN2008028825. OCLC233030259.

External links

Listen to this article (info/dl)


This audio file was created from a revision of the article 'Evolution' dated 2005-04-18, and does not reflect subsequent edits to the article. (Audio help)
General information
  • 'Evolution' on In Our Time at the BBC
  • 'Evolution'. New Scientist. ISSN0262-4079. Retrieved 2011-05-30.
  • 'Evolution Resources from the National Academies'. Washington, DC: National Academy of Sciences. Retrieved 2011-05-30.
  • 'Understanding Evolution: your one-stop resource for information on evolution'. Berkeley, California: University of California, Berkeley. Retrieved 2011-05-30.
  • 'Evolution of Evolution – 150 Years of Darwin's 'On the Origin of Species''. Arlington County, Virginia: National Science Foundation. Retrieved 2011-05-30.
  • 'Human Evolution Timeline Interactive'. Smithsonian Institution, National Museum of Natural History. 2010-01-28. Retrieved 2018-07-14. Adobe Flash required.
Experiments concerning the process of biological evolution
  • Lenski, Richard E. 'Experimental Evolution'. East Lansing, Michigan: Michigan State University. Retrieved 2013-07-31.
  • Chastain, Erick; Livnat, Adi; Papadimitriou, Christos; Vazirani, Umesh (July 22, 2014). 'Algorithms, games, and evolution'. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A.111 (29): 10620–10623. Bibcode:2014PNAS..11110620C. doi:10.1073/pnas.1406556111. ISSN0027-8424. PMC4115542. PMID24979793.
Online lectures
  • 'Evolution Matters Lecture Series'. Harvard Online Learning Portal. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University. Archived from the original on 2017-12-18. Retrieved 2018-07-15.
  • Stearns, Stephen C. 'EEB 122: Principles of Evolution, Ecology and Behavior'. Open Yale Courses. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University. Archived from the original on 2017-12-01. Retrieved 2018-07-14.
Retrieved from 'https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Evolution&oldid=909775619'
   Coments are closed